• Aucun résultat trouvé

Euclid's diagrammatic logic and cognitive science

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Partager "Euclid's diagrammatic logic and cognitive science"

Copied!
13
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

Cognitive Science

Yacin Hamami1and John Mumma2

1 Centre for Logic and Philosophy of Science, Vrije Universiteit Brussel, Brussels yacin.hamami@gmail.com

2 Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin john.mumma@gmail.com

Abstract. For more than two millennia, Euclid’sElementsset the stan- dard for rigorous mathematical reasoning. The reasoning practice the text embodied is essentially diagrammatic, and this aspect of it has been captured formally in a logical system termedEu[2, 3]. In this paper, we review empirical and theoretical works in mathematical cognition and the psychology of reasoning in the light ofEu. We argue that cognitive intuitions of Euclidean geometry might play a role in the interpretation of diagrams, and we show that neither the mental rules nor the mental models approaches to reasoning constitutes by itself a good candidate for investigating geometrical reasoning. We conclude that a cognitive framework for investigating geometrical reasoning empirically will have to account for both the interpretation of diagrams and the reasoning with diagrammatic information. The framework developed by Stenning and van Lambalgen [1] is a good candidate for this purpose.

1 Introduction

A distinctive feature of elementary Euclidean geometry is the natural and in- tuitive character of its proofs. The prominent place of the subject within the history and education of mathematics attests to this. It was taken to be the foundational starting point for mathematics from the time of its birth in ancient Greece up until the 19th century. And it remains within mathematics education as a subject that serves to initiate students in the method of deductive proof.

No other species of mathematical reasoning seem as basic and transparent as that which concerns the properties of figures in Euclidean space.

One may not expect a formal analysis of the reasoning to shed much light on this distinctive feature of it, as the formal and the intuitive are typically thought to oppose one another. Recently, however, a formal analysis, termed Eu, has been developed which challenges this opposition [2, 3]. Euis a formal proof system designed to show that a systematic method underlies the use of diagrams in Euclid’sElements, the representative text of the classical synthetic tradition of geometry. As diagrams seem to be closely connected with the way we call upon our intuition in the proofs of the tradition,Eu holds the promise of contributing to our understanding of what exactly makes the proofs natural.

(2)

In this paper, we explore the potentialEuhas in this respect by confronting it with empirical and theoretical works in the fields of mathematical cognition and the psychology of reasoning. Our investigation is organized around the two following issues:

1. What are the interpretative processes on diagrams involved in the reasoning practice of Euclidean geometry and what are their possible cognitive roots?

2. What would be an appropriate cognitive framework to represent and inves- tigate the constructive and deductive aspects of the reasoning practice of Euclidean geometry?

By providing a formal model of the reasoning practice of Euclidean geometry, Euprovides us with a tool to address these two issues. We proceed as follows. To address the first issue, we first state the interpretative capacities that according to the norms fixed byEuare necessary to extract, from diagrams, information for geometrical reasoning. We then present empirical works on the cognitive bases of Euclidean geometry, and suggest that cognitive intuitions might play a role in the interpretative aspects of diagrams in geometrical reasoning. To address the second issue, we compare the construction and inference rules of Eu with two major frameworks in the psychology of reasoning—the mental rules and the mental models theories. We argue that both have strengths and weaknesses as a cognitive account of geometrical reasoning as analyzed byEu, but that one will need to go beyond them to provide a framework for investigating geometrical reasoning empirically.

The two main issues are of course intimately related. In a last section, we argue that the framework developed by Stenning and van Lambalgen in [1], which connects interpretative and deductive aspects of reasoning, might provide the right cognitive framework for investigating the relation between them.

2 A Logical Analysis of the Reasoning Practice in Euclid’s Elements: The Formal System Eu

Euis based on the seminal paper [4] by Ken Manders. In [4] Manders challenges the received view that theElements is flawed because its proofs sometimes call upon geometric intuition rather than logic. What is left unexplained by the re- ceived view is the extraordinary longevity of the Elements as a foundational text within mathematics. For over two thousand years there were no serious challenges to its foundational status. Mathematicians through the centuries un- derstood it to display what the basic propositions of geometry are grounded on.

The deductive gaps that exist according to modern standards of logic story were simply not seen.

According to Manders, Euclid is not relying on geometric intuition illicitly in his proofs; he is rather employing a systematic method of diagrammatic proof.

His analysis reveals that diagrams serve a principled, theoretical role in Euclid’s mathematics. Only a restricted range of a diagram’s spatial properties are per- mitted to justify inferences for Euclid, and these self-imposed restrictions can be

(3)

explained as serving the purpose of mathematical control.Eu[2, 3] was designed to build on Manders’ insights, and precisely characterize the mathematical sig- nificance of Euclid’s diagrams in a formal system of geometric proof.

Euhas two symbol types: diagrammatic symbols∆and sentential symbolsA.

The sentential symbolsAare defined as they are in first-order logic. They express relations between geometric magnitudes in a configuration. The diagrammatic symbols are defined asn×narrays for anyn. Rules for a well-formed diagram specify how points, lines and circles can be distinguished within such arrays.

The points, lines and circles of Euclid’s diagrams thus have formal analogues in Eudiagrams. The positions the elements of Euclid’s diagrams can have to one another are modeled directly by the position their formal analogues can have within aEudiagram.

The content of a diagram within a derivation is fixed via a relation of dia- gram equivalence. Roughly, twoEudiagrams∆1and∆2 are equivalent if there is a bijection between its elements which preserves their non-metric positional relations.3 The equivalence relation is intended to capture what Manders terms theco-exact properties of a Euclidean diagram. A close examination of the El- ements shows that Euclid refrains from making any inferences that depend on a diagram’s metric properties. At the same time, Euclid does rely on diagrams for the non-metric positional relations they exhibit—or in Manders’ terms, the co-exact relations they exhibit. Diagrams, it turns out, can serve as adequate representations of such relations in proofs.

Eu exhibits this by depicting geometric proof as running on two tracks:

a diagrammatic one, and a sentential one. The role of the sentential one is to record metric information about the figure and provide a means for inferring this kind of information. The role of the diagrammatic track is to record non-metric positional information of the figure, and to provide a means for inferring this kind of information about it. Rules for building and transforming diagrams in derivations are sensitive only to properties invariant under diagram equivalence.

It is in this way that the relation of diagram equivalence fixes the content of diagrams in derivations.

What is derived inEuare expressions of the form

1, A1−→∆2, A2

where ∆1 and ∆2 are diagrams, and A1 and A2 are sentences. The geometric claim this is stipulated to express is the following:

?Given a configuration satisfying the non-metric positional relations de- picted in ∆1 and the metric relations expressed in A1, then one can obtain a configuration satisfying the positional relations depicted by∆2 and metric relations specified byA2.

3 For a more detailed discussion of Eu diagrams and diagram equivalence, we refer the reader respectively to sections A and B of the appendix.

(4)

3 Interpretative Aspects of Geometrical Reasoning with Diagrams

Diagrams in Euclid’sElements are mere pictures on a piece of paper. How can a visual experience triggered by looking at a picture lead to a cognitive representa- tion that can play a role in geometrical reasoning? From a cognitive perspective, taking seriously the use of diagrams in reasoning requires an account of the way diagrams are interpreted in order to play a role in geometrical reasoning.

The formal system Eu provides a theoretical answer to this question. Here we compare this theoretical account with recent works in mathematical cognition probing the existence of cognitive intuitions of Euclidean geometry. We will ar- gue that the Eu analysis of geometrical reasoning suggests a possible role for these cognitive intuitions in the interpretation of diagrams.

3.1 Interpretation of Diagrams in Eu

As described in section 2, the key insight behind theEuanalysis of the diagram- matic reasoning practice of Euclid’sElements is the observation that appeals to diagrams in proofs are highly controlled: proofs in Euclid’sElements only make use of the co-exact properties of diagrams. From a cognitive perspective, the practice of extracting the co-exact properties from a visual diagram is far from a trivial one. According toEu, the use of diagrams presupposes the two following cognitive abilities:

1. The capacity to categorize elements of the diagram using normative concepts:

points, linear elements and circles.

2. The capacity to abstract away irrelevant information from the visual-perceptual experience of the diagram.

The formal syntax ofEu, combined with the equivalence relation between Eu diagrams, can be interpreted as specifying these capacities precisely. More specifically:

– The first capacity amounts to the ability to see in the diagram the elements p, l,c of a particular Eudiagram hn, p, l, ci, which respectively denote the sets of points, lines and circles.

– The second capacity amounts to the ability to see in the particular diagram positional relations that are invariant under diagram equivalence.

Thus, the interpretation of a visual diagram according toEuresults in a for- mal object which consists in an equivalence class ofEudiagrams. It is precisely on these formal objects, the interpreted diagrams, that inference rules operate in theEuformalization of reasoning in elementary geometry.

3.2 Intuitions of Euclidean Geometry in Human Cognition

Recently, several empirical studies in mathematical cognition [5–7] have directly addressed the issue of the cognitive roots of Euclidean geometry. These studies

(5)

might be classified in two categories: one approach consists in providing empirical evidence for the existence ofabstract geometric concepts[5, 7], the other approach consists in providing empirical evidence for the perception ofabstract geometric features [6]. Here we successively report some of the empirical findings provided by these two approaches.

The two studies [5] and [7] have been conducted on an Amazonian Indi- gene Group called the Mundurucu, with no previous education in formal Eu- clidean geometry. In the first study [5], the experiment consisted in identifying the presence, or the absence, of several topological and geometric concepts in Mundurucu participants. To this end, the experimenter proposed, for each con- cept under investigation, six slides in which five of the images displayed the given geometric concept (e.g., parallelism), while the last one lacked the consid- ered property (non-parallel lines). The test shows that several basic geometrical concepts are present in Mundurucu conceptual systems, such as the concepts of straight line, parallel line, right angle, parallelogram, equilateral triangle, circle, center of circle. Nevertheless, the study [5] does not address geometric concepts that go beyond perceptual experience. Such concepts are the topic of another study [7]. In [7], empirical evidence is provided for the capacity of Mundurucu to reason about the properties of dots and infinite lines. In particular, most of the Mundurucu participants consider that, given a straight line and a dot, we can always position another straight line on the dot which will never cross the initial line.

The second approach for detecting the presence of intuitions of Euclidean geometry is based on the framework of transformational geometry [8]. Accord- ing to this framework, a geometric theory is identified with respect to the transformations that preserve its theorems. Euclidean geometry is then iden- tified by its four types of transformations—translation, rotation, symmetry and homothecy—leaving thenangleandlength proportions as the main defining fea- tures of figures in Euclidean geometry. The experimental approach based on this framework consists in investigating the capacity of participants to perceive ab- stract geometric features in configurations where irrelevant features are varied.

The experiments reported in [6] adopt such an approach. The empirical results show that both children and adults are able to use angle and size to classify shapes, but only adults are able to discriminate shapes with respect to sense, i.e., the property distinguishing two figures that are mirror images of each other.

The two approaches reported here to investigate cognitive intuitions of Eu- clidean geometry bring out cognitive abilities which seem related to the abilities for the interpretation of diagrams postulated byEu. This observation suggests a possible role for the cognitive intuitions of Euclidean geometry in the reasoning practice of elementary geometry, as we will now see.

3.3 Cognitive Intuitions and the Interpretation of Diagrams

How might the cognitive intuitions of Euclidean geometry relate to the deductive aspects of Euclid’s theory of geometry? In a correspondence in Science [9] on the study reported in [5], Karl Wulff has challenged the claim that Dehaeneet

(6)

al.address Euclidean geometry by denying a role for these cognitive intuitions in the demonstrative aspects of Euclid’s theory of geometry. An opposing position can be found in [10]:

The axioms of geometry introduced by Euclid [. . . ] define concepts with spatial content, such that any theorem or demonstration of Euclidean ge- ometry can be realized in the construction of a figure. Just as intuitions about numerosity may have inspired the early mathematicians to de- velop mathematical theories of number and arithmetic, Euclid may have appealed to universal intuitions of space when constructing his theory of geometry. [10, p. 320]

Interestingly, stating precisely the postulated cognitive abilities involved in the interpretation of diagrams according to Eu might suggest a role for the cognitive intuitions of Euclidean geometry in the reasoning practice of Euclid’s Elements.

Firstly, we have noticed that one of the key abilities in the interpretation of diagrams, according toEu, is the capacity tocategorize ortype the different figures of the visual diagram using the normative concepts of geometry. This ability seems to be universal, according to the empirical data that we reported in the previous section, as the Mundurucu people, without previous formal ed- ucation in Euclidean geometry, seem to possess an abstract conceptual systems which contains the key normative concepts of elementary geometry, and are able to use it to categorize elements of visual diagrams.

Secondly, interpretation of diagrams inEu requires an important capacity ofabstraction which is formally represented by an equivalence relation between diagrams. This equivalence relation aims to capture the idea that some features of the diagram are not relevant for reasoning: for instance, the same diagram rotated, translated or widened, would play exactly the same role in a geometrical proof of the Elements. This capacity of abstraction seems to connect with the cognitive ability of perceiving abstract geometric features, such as angle and length proportions, while abstracting away irrelevant information from the point of view of Euclidean geometry.

We now turn to the deductive and constructive aspects of geometrical reason- ing. In section 5, we argue that a plausible cognitive framework for an empirical investigation of geometrical reasoning will have to bring together the interpreta- tive, deductive and constructive aspects of geometrical reasoning to be faithful to the mathematical practice of Euclidean geometry.

4 Deductive and Constructive Aspects of Geometrical Reasoning with Diagrams

In this section, we begin by presenting the Eu formalization of constructive and deductive steps in Elementary geometry, and then discuss the capacity of the mental rules and the mental models theories to represent these reasoning steps. We conclude that an adequate framework for an empirical investigation of geometrical reasoning will have to go beyond these two theories.

(7)

4.1 Eu Construction and Inference Rules

TheEuproof rules specify how to derive ∆1, A1−→∆2, A2 expressions. They specify, in particular, the operations that can be performed on the pair∆1, A1

to produce a new pair∆2, A2. Given the intended interpretation of ∆1, A1−→

2, A2 given by ?, the fundamental restriction on these rules is that they be geometrically sound. In other words, if∆2, A2is derivable from∆,A1, then with any configuration satisfying the geometric conditions represented by∆1A1one must either have a configuration satisfying the conditions represented by∆2, A2 (if∆1 =∆2), or be able to construct a configuration satisfying the conditions represented by∆2, A2 (if∆2 contains objects not in∆1).

The formal process whereby∆2, A2is derived has two stages: a construction and demonstration. Hence Eu has two kinds of proof rules: construction rules and inference rules. The construction stage models the application of a proof’s construction on a given diagram. The demonstration stage models the inferences made from the assumed metric relations and the particular diagram produced by the construction. The soundness restriction thus applies only to the inference rules. The construction rules together codify a method for producing a represen- tation that can serve as a vehicle of inference. The demonstration rules codify the inferences that can be made from such a vehicle.4

4.2 Mental Rules Theory

The mental rules theory [11, 12] represents reasoning as the application offormal rules, rules which are akin to those of natural deduction. According to this theory, reasoning is conceived as a syntactic process whereby sentences are transformed.

These transformations are made according to specific rules defined precisely in terms of the syntactic structures of sentences. Deduction of one sentence from a set of other sentences (premisses) is seen as the search for a mental proof, which consists precisely in the production of the conclusion from the premisses by application of the rules a finite number of times. Consequently, the mental rules theory represents reasoning as consisting in syntactic operations on the logical forms of sentences.

The formalization of geometrical reasoning provided byEushares one impor- tant feature with the mental rules theory:Eu represents geometrical reasoning in terms of syntactic rules of inference. This is made possible by considering di- agrams as a kind ofsyntax, and then by stipulating rules that control inferences that are drawn from diagrams. Thus,Eudiagrams might be seen as representing something like thelogical form of concrete visual diagrams. One could perhaps say that Eu diagrams represent their geometric form, and that Eu inference rules operate on these forms. From this point of view, the formalization of ge- ometrical reasoning provided by Eu appears to be in direct line with the the mental rules theory of reasoning.

4 For the formal details, see sections 1.4.1 and 1.4.2 of [2], available online at www.johnmumma.org.

(8)

Nevertheless, the mental rules theory seems to run into troubles when we consider theconstruction operations on diagrams, which are central to the rea- soning practice of Euclidean geometry, and which are formalized by Eu’s con- struction rules. One might still argue that Eu construction rules are syntactic operations onEu diagrams, since diagrams are included its syntax, and soEu construction rules fit the framework of mental rules theory. However, this does not seem correct as the mental rules are considered to bededuction rules; the soundness restriction applies to them. They are thereby of a very different nature thanEu’s construction rules. Consequently, even though the mental rules theory could suitably represent inferential steps in geometrical reasoning, it seems that the theory lacks the necessary resources to account for the construction opera- tions on diagrams, an aspect fundamental to the reasoning practice in Euclidean geometry.

4.3 Mental Models Theory

The mental models theory [13, 14] postulates that reasoning depends on envisag- ingpossibilities. When given a set of premisses, an individual constructs mental models which correspond to the possibilities elicited by the premisses. Different reasoning strategies are then available to extract information from the mental models: one may represent several possibilities in a diagram and draw a conclu- sion from the diagram, one may make an inferential step from a single possibility, or one can use a possibility as a counter-example for falsifying a conclusion. One interesting feature of the theory is that mental models are supposed to beiconic:

the structure of a mental model is supposed to reflect the structure of the possi- bility that it represents. This feature is nicely illustrated when the mental models theory is applied to account for reasoning with visual-spatial information [15].

Contrary to the mental rules theory, the mental models theory seems suited to provide an account of the representation of the different construction opera- tions on diagrams: visual diagrams used in geometrical proofs can be conceived as mental models entertained by the reasoner. Mental models associated to di- agrams would then be of a visual-spatial nature, reflecting the spatial relations between the different elements of the diagram. This just seems to be a descrip- tion ofEudiagrams, which encode the information that can be legitimately used in geometrical reasoning.

Accordingly, ifEudiagrams are conceived as mental models, the construction operations on diagrams would be explained in terms of the ways mental models are constructed. Nevertheless, one might worry about the capacity of the mental models theory to account for the specific use of diagrams in geometrical rea- soning. One of the main points ofEuis to exhibit precisely that diagrammatic information enters legitimate mathematical inferences in a very controlled way.

In order to account for the use of diagrams in geometrical reasoning, the mental models theory would have to be supplemented with a regimentation of the in- formation that can be legitimately extracted from diagrams conceived as mental models. The formal systemEushows that this can be done using syntactic rules that operate on diagrams represented as syntactic objects.

(9)

4.4 Beyond the Mental Rules vs Mental Models Debate

Geometrical reasoning, as practiced in Euclid’sElements, constitutes an inter- esting test for current theories in the psychology of reasoning. Our previous comparison predicts that the mental rules and mental models theories present both advantages and disadvantages as an account of the reasoning practice of geometrical reasoning with diagrams. Indeed, it seems that these two theories are actually complementary in their capacity to account for geometrical reason- ing as described by Eu: the mental rules theory seems adequate to represent inferences in geometrical reasoning, while the mental models theory seems ade- quate to represent thediagrammatic constructions that support such inferences.

Thus, it seems that to provide a framework for an empirical investigation of geometrical reasoning with diagrams one will need to gobeyond these two theo- ries. Such a move is also suggested, although for different reasons, in [16, 17]. In this respect,Euconstitutes a possible starting point for developing a cognitive framework for geometrical reasoning which would be faithful to both deductive and constructive aspects of the mathematical practice of Euclidean geometry.

5 Interpretation and Reasoning in Elementary Geometry

According to the Euanalysis of geometrical reasoning, interpretation and rea- soning with diagrams are intimately related. This observation, originating in the study of the reasoning practice in Euclid’sElements [4], is directly in line with a recent approach to the psychology of reasoning developed by Stenning and van Lambalgen [1] which attributes a central role to interpretative processes in human reasoning:

We [. . . ] view reasoning as consisting of two stages: first one has to establish the domain about which one reasons and its formal properties (what we will call ‘reasoning to an interpretation’) and only after this initial step has been taken can ones reasoning be guided by formal laws (what we will call ‘reasoningfrom an interpretation’). [1, p. 28]

Geometrical reasoning with diagrams, as formalized by Eu, precisely fits within this framework: reasoning to an interpretation corresponds to the pro- cess of interpreting a visual diagram along with an associated metric assertion, resulting inEuinto a pair∆, A; reasoningfrom an interpretation is then repre- sented as the application of the formal rules of Euto prove geometric claims.

This perspective unifies the two main issues addressed in this paper. Our main conclusions can then be restated as follows: (i) intuitions of Euclidean geometry as studied by mathematical cognition are likely to play a role in reasoningtoan interpretation of a diagrams, (ii) the mental rules and mental models theories of reasoning are inadequate for representing reasoning from an interpretation, as none of them is able to account for both deductive and constructive aspects of geometrical reasoning. In the perspective of Stenning and van Lambalgen [1], Euappears as a good candidate for representing the process of reasoning from an interpretation in elementary geometry.

(10)

6 Conclusion

The empirical investigation of the cognitive bases of Euclidean geometry is a multi-disciplinary enterprise involving both mathematical cognition and the psy- chology of reasoning, and which shall benefit from works in formal logic and the nature of mathematical practice. In this paper, we used the formal systemEuto review existing empirical and theoretical works in cognitive science with respect to this enterprise. Our investigation shows: (i) the necessity of dealing jointly with interpretation and reasoning, (ii) the relevance of works on the cognitive bases of Euclidean geometry for the interpretation of diagrams and (iii) the ne- cessity to go beyond the mental rules vs mental models distinction for accounting for both constructive and deductive aspects of geometrical reasoning.

References

1. Stenning, K., Van Lambalgen, M.: Human Reasoning and Cognitive Science. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (2008)

2. Mumma, J.: Intuition Formalized: Ancient and Modern Methods of Proof in Ele- mentary Geometry. PhD thesis, Carnegie Mellon University (2006)

3. Mumma, J.: Proofs, pictures, and Euclid. Synthese175(2) (2010) 255–287 4. Manders, K.: The Euclidean diagram. In Mancosu, P., ed.: Philosophy of Mathe-

matical Practice. Clarendon Press, Oxford (2008)

5. Dehaene, S., Izard, V., Pica, P., Spelke, E.: Core knowledge of geometry in an Amazonian indigene group. Science311(5759) (2006) 381–384

6. Izard, V., Spelke, E.: Development of sensitivity to geometry in visual forms.

Human Evolution23(3) (2009) 213–248

7. Izard, V., Pica, P., Spelke, E., Dehaene, S.: Flexible intuitions of Euclidean geom- etry in an Amazonian indigene group. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences108(24) (2011) 9782–9787

8. Klein, F.: A comparative review of recent researches in geometry. Bulletin of the New York Mathematical Society2(1893) 215–249

9. Wulff, K.: Examining knowledge of geometry. Science312(5778) (2006) 1309 10. Izard, V., Pica, P., Dehaene, S., Hinchey, D., Spelke, E.: Geometry as a universal

mental construction. In Brannon, E., Dehaene, S., eds.: Space, Time and Number in the Brain: Searching for the Foundations of Mathematical Thought. Number XXIV in Attention & Performance. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2011) 319–

332

11. Rips, L.: Cognitive processes in propositional reasoning. Psychological Review 90(1) (1983) 38–71

12. Rips, L.: The Psychology of Proof: Deductive Reasoning in Human Thinking. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1994)

13. Johnson-Laird, P.: Mental Models. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1983) 14. Johnson-Laird, P.: Mental models and human reasoning. Proceedings of the Na-

tional Academy of Sciences107(43) (2010) 18243–18250

15. Knauff, M.: A neuro-cognitive theory of deductive relational reasoning with mental models and visual images. Spatial Cognition & Computation9(2) (2009) 109–137 16. Knauff, M.: How our brains reason logically. Topoi26(1) (2007) 19–36

17. Goel, V.: Anatomy of deductive reasoning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences11(10) (2007) 435–441

(11)

Appendix

A Eu diagrams

The syntactic structure of diagrams in Eu has no natural analogue in stan- dard logic. Their underlying form is a square array of dots of arbitrary finite dimension.

The arrays provide the planar background for an Eu diagram. Within them geometric elements—points, linear elements, and circles— are distinguished. A point is simply a single array entry. An example of a diagram with a single point in it is

Linear elements are subsets of array entries defined by linear equations expressed in terms of the array entries. (The equation can be bounded. If it is bounded on one side, the geometric element is a ray. If it is bounded on two sides, the geometric element is a segment.) An example of a diagram with a point and linear element is

(12)

Finally, a circle is a convex polygon within the array, along with a point inside it distinguished as its center. An example of a diagram with a point, linear element and a circle is

The size of a diagram’s underlying array and the geometric elements distin- guished within it, comprise a diagram’s identity. Accordingly, a diagram inEu is a tuple

hn, p, l, ci

where n, a natural number, is the length of the underlying array’s sides, and p, l and c are the sets of points, linear elements and circles of the diagram, respectively.

Like the relation symbols which comprise metric assertions, the diagrams have slots for variables. A diagram in which the slots are filled is termed alabeled diagram. The slots a diagram has depends on the geometric elements constituting it. In particular, there is a place for a variable beside a point, beside the end of a linear element (which can be an endpoint or endarrow), and beside a circle.

One possible labeling for the above diagram is thus

A

B C

E D

Having labeled diagrams within Euis essential, for otherwise it would be im- possible for diagrams and metric assertions to interact in the course of a proof.

We can notate any labeled diagram as

hn, p, l, ci[A, R]

whereAdenotes a sequence of variables andRa rule matching each variable to each slot in the diagram.

(13)

B Diagram equivalence

The definition of diagram equivalence is based on the notions of a diagram’s completionand that ofco-exact map. The completion∆0of a diagram∆is simply the diagram obtained by adding to ∆ intersection points to the intersections present in it. (See page 38-40 of [2]) Two diagrams are then equivalent if there is a co-exact map between their completions.

The key idea behind the definition of diagram equivalence, then, is that of of a co-exact map. A necessary condition for their to be such a map between diagrams∆1and∆2is that both diagrams contain the same number of points, linear elements and circles, and these objects are labeled by the same variables and variable pairs.

Suppose∆1and∆2are two such diagrams, andφxis the bijection that maps an element in ∆1 to the element in ∆2 with the same label. In virtue of their position with respect to the underlying array of∆1, the elements of ∆1 satisfy various geometric relations. The bijectionφxis a co-exact map if and only if it preserves a certain sub-set of these relations. Precisely φx is a co-exact map if and only if it satisfies the following nine conditions, where P andQ are points of∆1,N andM are linear elements of∆1 (i.e. segments, rays, or lines) andC1

andC2 are circles of∆1.

– P lies onM in∆1←→φx(P) lies onφx(M) in∆2.

– P andQlie on a given sideM in∆1←→φx(P) andφx(Q) lie on the same side of φx(M) in ∆2. (The same side of φx(M) in is determined via the orientation specified by the two variable label ofM andφx(M).)

– P lies inside/on/outside circle C1 in ∆1 ←→ φx(P) lies inside/on/outside φx(C1) in∆2.

– M intersects N at a point/along a segment in ∆1 ←→ φx(M) intersects φx(N) at a point/along a segment in∆2.

– M cuts in one point/cuts in two points/is tangent at one point to/is tangent along a segment to C1 in ∆1 ←→ φx(M) cuts in one point/cuts in two points/is tangent at one point to/is tangent along a segment toφx(C1) in

2.

– C1has the same intersection signature with respect toC2in∆1asφx(C1) has with respect toφx(C2) in∆2. (The intersection signature classifies the way C1andC2intersect each other as convex polygons. For its precise definition, see appendix A in the thesis.)

– Circle C1 lies outside/ is contained by circle C2 in ∆1 ←→ φx(C1) lies outside/is contained by circleφx(C2) in∆2.

– Circle C1 lies within a given side of M in ∆1 ←→ φx(C1) lies within the same side ofφx(M) in ∆2.

– End-arrowP is on a given side ofM in ∆1 ←→φx(P) is on the same side ofφx(M) in∆2.

Références

Documents relatifs

Hand can be thought of as the most basic interface for interacting in our environment (Treadaway, 2009), allowing to feel afferent and efferent information during exploration

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des

Our main conclusions can then be restated as follows: (i) intuitions of Euclidean geometry as studied by mathematical cognition are likely to play a role in reasoning to

The objectives of the group are to review the current state of scientific knowledge about virology, diagnostics, clinical features, epidemiology, and the impact of disease

13 There are technical advisors in the following areas: Chronic Disease & Mental Health; Communication & Media; Entomology (vacant); Environmental Health;

We say that (s, τ) is decorated if each vertex v of s is associated with an elementary star F v , and a “gluing” application that maps the half-edges of s adjacent to v to the

Then we gave a brief discussion of the logical systems of natural logic, to present logical systems which are sound and complete, have low computational overhead, and which are

Based on this representation, Section 4 discusses how beliefs and back- ground knowledge influences the reasoning process and shows that the results can be modeled by computing