• Aucun résultat trouvé

Modelling under ambiguity with dynamically consistent Choquet random walks and Choquet-Brownian motions

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "Modelling under ambiguity with dynamically consistent Choquet random walks and Choquet-Brownian motions"

Copied!
10
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-02633613

https://hal.inrae.fr/hal-02633613

Submitted on 27 May 2020

HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers.

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés.

Distributed under a Creative CommonsAttribution - NonCommercial - NoDerivatives| 4.0 International License

Modelling under ambiguity with dynamically consistent Choquet random walks and Choquet-Brownian motions

Robert Kast, André Lapied, David Roubaud

To cite this version:

Robert Kast, André Lapied, David Roubaud. Modelling under ambiguity with dynamically consistent Choquet random walks and Choquet-Brownian motions. Economic Modelling, Elsevier, 2014, 38 (C), pp.495-503. �10.1016/j.econmod.2014.01.007�. �hal-02633613�

(2)

Modelling under ambiguity with dynamically consistent Choquet random walks and Choquet – Brownian motions

Robert Kasta, André Lapiedb, David Roubaudc,

aCNRS, LAMETA-INRA, 2 place Viala, F. 34 060 Cedex 1, Montpellier, France

bAix-Marseille University (Aix-Marseille School of Economics), CNRS & EHESS, Aix-Marseille Université, 3 avenue Robert Schuman, 13628 Aix-en-Provence, France

cGroupe Sup de Co Montpellier Business School, Montpellier Research in Management, Montpellier Business School, 2300 Avenue des Moulins, 34185 Montpellier, France

a b s t r a c t a r t i c l e i n f o

Article history:

Accepted 6 January 2014 Available online 26 February 2014

JEL classification:

D81 D83 D92 G31

Keywords:

Ambiguity models Choquet–Brownian motion Random walk

Dynamic consistency Capacities

Ambiguity is pervasive in many environments and is increasingly being introduced into economic andfinancial models. This paper characterises ambiguity in the form of newly defined Choquet random walks: discrete-time binomial trees with capacities instead of exact probabilities on their branches. We describe the axiomatic basis of Choquet random walks, including dynamic consistency. We also discuss the convergence of Choquet random walks to Choquet–Brownian motion in continuous time. In contrast to previous literature, we derive tractable stochastic processes that allow for a wide range of ambiguity preferences to be represented in continuous time (including ambiguity-seeking preferences). Finally, we apply Choquet–Brownian ambiguity to a model of sta- tionary inter-temporal portfolio choice. Wefind that both the mean and the variance of the underlying stochastic process are modied. This result opens the way for qualitative and quantitative results that differ from those of standard expected utility models and other models that feature ambiguity.

© 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V.

1. Introduction

Models that involve uncertainty typically assume that uncertainty parameters should take the familiar form of risk (i.e., a probability mea- sure). Consequently, in continuous-time applications, the dynamics of a risky variable (such as the cashows of a project) are often described by some known stochastic processes such as Brownian motion. However, uncertainty is a rich and complex concept that may not be limited to risk.

Indeed, alternative ways of characterising uncertainty are some- times required in model construction, especially when the nature of the uncertainty prevalent in a given environment is not fully captured by standard risk parameters. This need has led to the development of models that incorporate ambiguity parametrically. Ambiguity may, for instance, result from different perceptions among individuals of the sources of uncertainty or from incomplete information/transparency.

In the economic andnancial modelling literature, the signicance of

ambiguity is increasingly recognised, with ambiguity parameters being introduced into a growing body of fruitful models.1

Nevertheless, how best to model ambiguity remains controver- sial at the axiomatic and theoretical level, as well as in practice. Let us recall that in the presence of risk, it is possible to use the objective expected utility maximisation model or, in the absence of a comput- able or observable probability distribution, its subjective version. Ex- pected utility models are extremely tractable and allow for the construction ofexible yet sound models. However, in contexts that feature ambiguity, these standards models cannot be used with- out ignoring a whole range of behaviours and preferences. This limit has been repeatedly identied experimentally and in many empiri- cal studies (sinceEllsberg, 1961).

To address this challenge, ambiguity has, since the 1980s, been repre- sented by mathematical concepts in decision theory. Several axiomatic

Corresponding author. Tel.: +33 6 51080876.

E-mail address:d.roubaud@supco-montpellier.fr(D. Roubaud).

1Incorporating ambiguous rather than just risky uncertainty parameters into models was shown to substantially impact individual choices and the resulting macro-economic equilibrium conditions (Dow and Verlang, 1992; Epstein and Wang, 1994). This has al- ready led to reinterpretations of well-knownfinancial puzzles, such as the“equity premi- um”puzzle or the“home bias”puzzle (on the reinterpretations offinancial puzzles, see the review on ambiguity and asset pricing inGuidolin and Rinaldi, 2011).

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.econmod.2014.01.007 0264-9993 © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V.

Contents lists available atScienceDirect

Economic Modelling

j o u r n a l h o m e p a g e : w w w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / e c m o d

Open access under CC BY-NC-ND license.

Open access under CC BY-NC-ND license.

(3)

bases have been proposed and applied. In particular, the multiple-priors model ofGilboa and Schmeidler (1989)was a signicant breakthrough, especially as it was successfully expanded to a continuous time setting (Chen and Epstein, 2002). The multiple-priors model is based on the maxmincriterion, implying optimisation in a worst case scenario.

However, it is remarkable that pioneer models of ambiguity, such as the multiple-priors model, focus exclusively on ambiguity-adverse agents. This is indeed a reasonable assumption in many situations where agents focus on worst-case scenarios to determine their optimal decisions. However, even if ambiguity aversion may usually prevail among agents, it does not fully account for the variety of observed indi- vidual behaviours and choices that occur in situations that feature ambiguity.

Although several models expand the domain of acceptable prefer- ences to account for a wider range of attitudes towards ambiguity,2 most of these alternative models, such as those inSchroder (2008)or Kim et al. (2009), are not dynamically consistent.3Even the very prom- ising model of smooth ambiguity suffers from constraints that may sig- nicantly undermine its usefulness in modelling.4This impairs, to a certain extent, its potential application to model construction and it may be complemented by other representations of ambiguity such as ours.

The methodology of our paper derives from two preliminary obser- vations: a) while far from perfect, Brownian motion is still widely used in economic andnancial models (for instance, to describe the dynam- ics of cashows in the real investment literature), and b) existing ambi- guity models almost always focus exclusively on worst-case scenarios by adopting the multiple-priors model. In many contexts, this repre- sents an excessive limitation on the domain of admissible individual preferences in the presence of ambiguity.

In light of these two observations, the goal of this paper is twofold.

First, we preserve the representation of ambiguity in the Brownian mo- tion model5to derive a tool that should be tractable enough to be ap- plied in many settings (as initiated by Epstein's multiple-priors models). Adopting Brownian motion also helps us compare ourndings with those of multiple-priors models. To construct ambiguous geomet- ric Brownian motion, we start with a simple binomial process measured by a capacity6(rather than a probability). We then show that this pro- cess converges to a type of Brownian motion. This approach differs from the multiple-priors approach, which directly considers a family of Brownian motion processes.

Second, we allow for a wider range of individual ambiguity prefer- ences to be explicitly included (i.e. ambiguity seeking as well as aver- sion). To do so, we use capacities, rather than standard probabilities, to weight the perceived likelihood of ambiguous outcomes. The use of capacities allows us to expand the domain of acceptable preferences re- garding ambiguity to a wider range than is permitted by such models as the multiple-priors model.

Let us clarify what we mean by uncertainty, as subjectively mea- sured by the decision maker: we mean that there is not necessarily an objective level of ambiguity that is observed independently of one's

preferences with respect to objective ambiguity, as in the smooth ambi- guity models. We rely on discounted Choquet expected utility7to value alternatives and decide between ambiguous outcomes.

This paper thus offers a tractable alternative to the existing powerful ambiguity aversion models by relying on some properties of Choquet integrals and capacities, as adapted to stochastic processes. Our paper denes ambiguous random walks and Brownian processes in a Choquet expected utility framework. An earlier unpublished version of this work (Kast and Lapied, 2010a) has been applied to real investment decisions (Roubaud et al., 2010) and to assessments of environmental policy op- tions (Agliardi and Sereno, 2011).

In this paper, we also show that the binomial processes constructed are dynamically consistent, which is an interesting (and often neces- sary!) property of economic andnancial models. Without this proper- ty, the model would be seriously limited. However, even with it, if one is not careful, the model may still collapse into an additive model (Sarin and Wakker, 1998) and hence lose its relevance to the issue of ambigu- ity. One way out of this difculty is to consider only binomial recursive models (one period ahead) instead of the full dynamic model. This is the method adopted in this paper, in accordance with themaxminrecursive expected utility approach, as it enables us to address most of the model- ling problems that arise.

The remainder of the paper is organised as follows. InSection 2, we build the axiomatic basis for Choquet random walks. Specically, uncer- tainty is described by a binomial tree measured by the same capacity on the up and down branches. We show how individual preferences over payoff processes may be represented by a discounted Choquet expecta- tion that satises model consistency and a weakened version of dynam- ic consistency. This opens the way for discrete-time applications of Choquet ambiguity. InSection 3, we investigate the limit behaviour of the joint capacity when time intervals converge to zero to allow for continuous-time modelling. We obtain a type of Brownian motion as the limit of the Choquet binomial random walk. InSection 4, we apply ChoquetBrownian ambiguity to a model of stationary inter-temporal portfolio choice. InSection 5, we relate our results to similar results in the literature and conclude.

2. Dynamically consistent binomial Choquet random walks 2.1. Method

As a starting point, we consider a particular belief represented by a non-additive measure, the Choquet capacity. Because it is non- additive, this measure may be interpreted as revealing the attitude of a decision maker towards the evolution over time of the value of a par- ticular process that is perceived as ambiguous. As noted above, our ap- proach is axiomatic and subjective (the measure derives exclusively from the decision maker's preferences), without reference to an objec- tive probability distribution that would be subjectively distorted.

There is no need for anobjectivesource of ambiguity, in response to which the decision maker would take a particular stance. We directly introduce the ambiguity preference into the dynamics of the ambiguity parameter.

Werst consider a familiar discrete time dynamic model that we as- sume to be ambiguous, an ambiguous random walk (or Choquet ran- dom walk). InSection 3, we show that it converges to a continuous time model, an ambiguous type of Wiener process that we call a ChoquetBrownian motion. First, however, how we dene a Choquet random walk.

Consider a standard random walk that may be represented in a typical binomial decision tree. Suppose also thatupanddownmove- ments across the decision tree have the same magnitude and likelihood

2 See theα-MEU (Ghirardato et al., 2004) or the neo-additive capacities (Chateauneuf et al., 2007).

3 Dynamic consistency implies that the decision maker, once he commits to a contin- gent plan, does not later change his plans. To meet this condition, it is sufficient to allow the use of a dynamic programming principle (Riedel, 2009). On the normative side, such a condition also intuitively appears to be a key requirement for rational behaviour over time.

4 The smooth ambiguity model (Klibanoff et al., 2005, 2009) assumes separation be- tween beliefs and tastes through a second-order functional. But its extension to continu- ous time has not yet been clearly established.Skiadas (2014)shows that in continuous time, the smooth ambiguity adjustment may vanish and fail to preserve the ambiguity preferences.

5 Another alternative approach where vagueness is incorporated in Geometric Brownian motions infinancial models (through fuzzy sets) was proposed inAgliardi and Agliardi (2009).

6 The key characteristic of a capacity is that it is non-additive (Choquet, 1954).

7 SeeSchmeidler (1986, 1989),Gilboa (1987), andSarin and Wakker (1992). Let us re- call that when beliefs are represented by capacities, a specific notion of integration, the Choquet integral, is required, which takes into account the rank of outcomes.

(4)

of occurrence (denoted asc). This is the basic description of a symmetric Choquet random walk.8

To characterise a Choquet random walk, we rely on the use of capac- ities rather than probabilities.9A capacity summarises preferences re- garding ambiguity by measuring the likelihood of up and down movements (rather than by assigning standard probability measures).

In a Choquet random walk, if the capacity is convex10(ambiguity aver- sion11), then the value attributed to a fair game (the same likelihood for up and down movements, where the movements are of the same mag- nitude in absolute terms) is negative, due to the use of Choquet integrals to compute the value, which is sufcient to account for ambiguity pref- erences (in contrast with the probabilistic case, where the value of a fair game is zero). The opposite holds if the capacity is concave (ambiguity seeking).

Graphically, a symmetric Choquet random walk may be represented as follows:

Ambiguity is introduced at each node of the binomial tree, determin- ing the likelihood of movement up or down. Without loss of generality, we take the increments to be unity (1, +1) and the departure point to be zero. The uncertain states,s1,,sninSare trajectories or sequences of nodes in the tree.

For any nodestat datet(0tbT), ifsut+ 1andsdt+ 1are the two possible successors ofstat datet+ 1 (for, respectively, anupor a

downmovement in the binomial tree), the conditional capacity is a constant:ν(stu+ 1/st) =ν(std+ 1/st) =c, with 0bcb1.

The value of the parametercis fundamental, as it summarises the decision maker's attitude towards ambiguity. It represents an index of the individual's preferences regarding ambiguity. Ifc¼12, then we are back to the probabilistic case.

In summary, we consider a modied version of a standard binomial tree, where uncertain states are represented through sequences of nodes describing the trajectories of the random variable, and whereca- pacitiesrather than probabilities represent preferences. Thus, the dy- namics of such an uncertain random variable may be described by a discrete time Brownian motion process, in which probability 1/2 is

replaced by a constant12c(the ambiguous weight that the decision maker places both on the eventupand the eventdowninstead of the unambiguous 1/2).

2.2. Insuring dynamic consistency

The construction of the axiomatic basis for Choquet random walks is described in detail in Appendices. Itrst includes the dynamic consisten- cy axioms and the conditions expressing consistency between condition- al and unconditional expectations, as characterised inProposition 1and relation(1)inAppendix 1.

Proposition 1.Under the representation of preferences satisfying our six axioms, for any XRS × T,∀τ{0,,Τ},iI,[Yτ= i]Fτ,t,τt

T, Eνð Þ ¼Xt EνhE½νYτ¼ið ÞXti . Proof.SeeAppendix 1.

FromProposition 1, dynamic consistency implies (seeAppendix 1):

∀τ¼1;…;T1;t

¼τ;…;T;X

sτSτ

½X

stSt

Xtð Þst Δνðst=sτÞΔνð Þ ¼sτ X

stSt

Xtð Þst Δνð Þst : ð1Þ

The axiomatic basis allows for the characterisation of subjective ca- pacity as follows:

Proposition 2. A dynamically consistent Choquet random walk that sat- ises relation(1)is completely dened by a unique capacityνsatisfying:

νsutþ1=st

¼νsdtþ1=st

¼c: ð2Þ

Proof.SeeAppendix 2.

The idea is that, in our binomial lattice, theltration isxed and then, we can only consider comonotonic payoffs (on a comonotonic cone). Therefore, on the binomial tree, the capacity is equivalent to a unique probability. This identication is correct because we dene non-conditional capacities from given conditional capacities and not the reverse.

Proposition 3. In a dynamically consistent Choquet random walk, the ca- pacityνis sub-linear if and only if c1/2. Moreover, it does not reduce to a probability if and only if c1/2.

Proof.SeeAppendix 3.

Sublinear is implied by convexity but not equivalent.

A2S;v Sð Þ ¼1v Að Þ þv AC :

The decision maker consider a fair game whenc= 1/2.

Ifcb1/2, the sum of one $ ifAis drawn and one $ ifACis drawn is less than one $ with certainty (Schmeidler's uncertainty aversion).

2.3. Choquet expectation of symmetric Choquet random walks

To compute the Choquet expectation of such a process (which is re- quired to provide a decision criterion), we must characterise the A binomial Choquet random walk based on capacity c.

8Symmetric random walks are binomial processes where‘up’and‘down’movements correspond to the same weight. In the probabilistic model, i.e., the case wherec= 1/2, this process is a discrete time Brownian motion.

9We are not trying here to model distortions of probabilitiesstricto sensu, which is an- other vision of the potential impact of ambiguity. Such distortions, such as the tendency to overweight small probabilities, have been widely documented in the literature.

10A convex capacity on afinite set of states of natureSis a real-valued set function on the subsets ofSsuch that:∀A,B2S,ν(AB) +ν(AB)≥ν(A) +ν(B). Choquet defined the concept in 1953, with some additional continuity requirements, that are actually satisfied whenSisfinite.

11A behavioural interpretation of capacities (Schmeidler, 1989) leads to representing a wide range of attitudes towards ambiguity (as concavity with≤instead of≥in the expres- sion above may represent ambiguity loving).

12The model is robust to a non-constantcif the conditional capacities have given values.

The non-conditional capacities can be deduced from these values. But, ifcis non constant, the symmetry required from a fair game disappear and then the formalization of the ran- dom walk. Moreover the calculus is no more tractable!

(5)

decumulativedistribution function of capacityν. The decumulative func- tion of capacityνis obtained by iteration:

t¼2;…;T;n¼1;…;t;ν s1t;…;snt

¼cνs1t−1;…;snt−1

þð1cÞνs1t−1;…;snt−11

ð3: andν(s11) =c.

The closed form of the decumulative function is:

t¼1;…;T;n¼1;…;t1; νs1t;snt

¼ct−nþ1Xn−1

j¼0

j tnþj

1c

ð Þj: ð3:

Proof.SeeAppendix 4.

Remark.The binomial tree should bepath independent(for exam- ple,up then downnodes correspond todown then upnodes). Con- sequentlyn=t(i.e., the number of nodes equals the date at each period). Indeed with a path dependent lattice, it is not possible to deter- mine a unique capacity as inProposition 2, because, in this case, the dy- namic consistency formula leads to different values at timetfrom the followingupanddownnodes.

Proposition 4. The Choquet expectation of the payoffs at date t of a sym- metric Choquet random walk is:

t¼0;…;T; E Xð Þ ¼t tð2c1Þ: ð4Þ

Proof.SeeAppendix 5.

Remarks.cb1/2E(Xt)b0. This is consistent with ambiguity aver- sion as it results in the attribution of a negative expected value to a fair game. Furthermore, other symmetric random walks can be obtained from this one by a positive afne transformation. The Choquet integral is linear with respect to such a transformation.

Fort= 0,,T,Yt=a Xt+b,aN0, we have:E(Yt) =a t(2c1) +b.

As a result, if required by modelling considerations, we can ad- dress cases where the mean is nonzero and allow volatility to vary.

It may be useful to clarify the link between dynamically con- sistent Choquet random walks and the recursive multiple-priors model ofEpstein and Schneider (2003). For a convex or concave capacity, as shown above, it is easy to exhibit the possible condi- tional one-step-ahead priors, making our model recursive. More- over, we have shown that if c1/2, the convex core of capacity νis the convex and rectangular set of priors in the multiple- priors model.

The literature on dynamic risk measures is also very close to this method. Risk is measured, at timet, by the maximum of the expecta- tions minus the sum of discounted cash-ows, with respect to the prob- abilities in a closed and convex set, conditional on information at timet.

This result is obtained, given certain properties: coherence, dynamic consistency and relevancy (seeRiedel, 2004, Theorem 1). The crucial one, consistency, is equivalent to rectangularity in Epstein and Schneider's model (2003).

3. Convergence to ChoquetBrownian motion

Choquet random walks can be used in discrete-time modelling in the presence of ambiguity, but we consider their expansion to continu- ous time. In this section, we show that when the time interval converges to zero, the Choquet binomial model converges to a deformed Brownian

motion, where both the drift and the volatility are modied, in contrast with theChen and Epstein (2002)recursive multiple-priors model, where only the volatility is modied.

Let usrst characterise the variations of thedecumulativefunction of the previously dened dynamically consistent Choquet random walk.

Proposition 5.

t¼1;…;T;n¼1;…;tþ1;

Δνntþ1¼cΔνntþð1cÞΔνn−1t

Δνntνs1t;snt

−νs1t;sn−1t

¼ n1 t

ct−nþ1ð1cÞn−1 ð5Þ

where we set:ν(st0) = 0.

Proof.SeeAppendix 6.

Proposition 6. When the time interval converges to 0, the symmetric random walk, dened by Eq.(5), converges to a general Wiener process, with mean m = 2c1 and variance s2= 4c(1c).

Proof.SeeAppendix 7.

3.1. Discussion of properties and sensitivity analysis

The resulting Brownian motion exhibits some interesting properties.

Note that ifcb1/2, thenmb0 ands2b1: both the mean and the variance are smaller than in the probabilistic model. Indeed, ambiguity aversion yields smaller weights on the up and down movements (cb1/2), for given value increments (+1,1); hence, the variance is smaller.

The sensitivity of the ChoquetBrownian motion with respect to the main value drivers may be further illustrated through a numerical appli- cation. Let us recallrst that anincreasein aversion (orlove) towards perceived ambiguity in our setting means that the value of parameterc is going further away from its central key anchor 1/2 (corresponding to the limit probabilistic case, that of an absence of ambiguity). Possible deviations are consequently conned in a range and c represents the index of the intensity and nature of the attitude towards perceived ambiguity.

SupposeBis a standard Brownian motion andμ′andσ′are some real numbers, withμ′=μ+mσ,σ′=sσ,m= 2c1,s2= 4c(1c),μN 0 andσN0. In the graph below, we see how a change in the value of pa- rametercimpacts both the driftμ′and volatilityσ′of the Choquet Brownian motion (whereμandσcorrespond to the initial values for the drift and volatility before the introduction of ambiguity). The con- trast between the nature of the impact on the drift and on the volatility appears clearly.

Sensitivity of key drivers to a change in ambiguity preferences (based on initial valuesμ= 2 andσ= 5).

(6)

Remark. The absence of ambiguity (or the neutrality towards ambigu- ity) is the case where:c= 0.5 (obviously in that case in the numerical illustration aboveμ′=μ= 2 andσ′=σ= 5).

Before applying this model (inSection 4) and comparing it with the multiple-priors model (inSection 5), we conclude this section with a remark on the convergence of ChoquetBrownian motions.

The notion ofstochastic convergenceformalises the idea that a se- quence of essentially random or unpredictable events can some- times be expected to settle into a pattern. However, the notion of convergence of a distribution is very frequently used in practice;

most often, it arises from application of the central limit theorem.

SeeBillingsley (1999)andJacod and Shiryaev (2002)for detailed discussions of convergence concepts.

Let us emphasise that, in our representation, in a cone with comonotonic variables, we obtain a probabilistic representation and thus can use the traditional results on statistical convergence. Further- more, observe that, in the multiple-priors model, Chen and Epstein avoid addressing convergence directly by employing, in continuous- time, an analogy with discrete-time. This has not prevented widespread use of the multiple-priors approach in economic andnancial model- ling. Finally, our representation is close to that of the multiple-priors model, with the symmetrical case of concavity of capacities added to the usual case of convexity.

4. Applications

Following earlier versions of this paper, a few applications of ChoquetBrownian motion have been proposed, showing signicant and contrasting effects of ambiguity. They have addressed real in- vestment decisions (the optimal timing and valuation of real op- tions, as in Roubaud et al. (2010)) and the optimal timing of environmental policies (Agliardi and Sereno, 2011). The former ex- tends the real options theory and method (Dixit and Pindyck, 1994; Trigeorgis, 1996) by modelling ambiguous cashows expect- ed from an investment project.

Agliardi and Sereno use ChoquetBrownian ambiguity to explore the optimal timing of environmental policies, such as taxes and non- tradable quotas, in the presence of ambiguity about the future costs and benets of such policies.

In this paper, we now suggest the application of our model to the op- timal portfolio choice of traded assets. We consider a stationary version of the inter-temporal Capital Asset Pricing Model (Merton, 1969, 1971, 1973).

Let (w(t))0tT, the wealth of the investor, which has to be allocated between a riskless asset with constant instantaneous rate of returnr,rN0, and a risky asset the price of whom follows a ChoquetBrownian motion:

dP tð Þ ¼mP tð ÞdtþσP tð ÞdB tð Þ ð6Þ

withP(0)N0, whereBis a standard Brownian motion andμ′andσ′are some real numbers, withμ′=μ+mσ,σ′=sσ,m= 2c1,s2= 4c (1c),μN0 andσN0.

(x(t)) is the part of the capital invested in the risky asset at datetand then the following Stochastic differential equation characterises the agent's wealth:

dw tð Þ

w tð Þ ¼x tð ÞdP tð Þ

P tð Þ þ½1x tð Þrdt: ð7Þ

The programme of the agent for a time horizonTis to maximise the expected utility of hisnal wealth:

x tð ÞMax

ð Þ0≤t≤T

Et½u w Tð ð ÞÞ;wð Þ0 N0 ð8Þ

whereu(.) is an increasing and concave utility function, with respect to the following SDE straightforwardly obtained with Eqs.(6) and (7):

dw tð Þ ¼rþx tð Þμ0r

w tð Þdtþσ0x tð Þw tð ÞdB tð Þ: ð9Þ In the well-known iso-elastic case:u wð Þ ¼w1−α1−α,αN0,α1, where the constantαis the relative risk aversion coefcient, the optimal solu- tion is a constant:

x∗ðt;wÞ ¼x¼1 α μr

σ02

!

: ð10Þ

If 0bcb1/2, we haveμσbμ′bμand 0bσ′bσ, and if 1/2bcb1, we haveμbμ′bμ+σand 0bσ′bσ.

Ifxcharacterises the optimal solution without ambiguity (c= 1/2), it is easy to check that:

xbx⇔λμ−r σ b− m

1s2¼ 1 12c:

The value of the market price of riskλrelatively to the ambiguity pa- rametercgives the hierarchy between investment in the risky asset with or without ambiguity.

Similarly:

x

cN0⇔λμ−r

σ b12cþ2c2 12c :

Let usrst underline that the impact of risk aversion itself on the op- timal choice is straightforward: the quantity of risky asset is inversely proportional to the relative risk aversion coefcientαin relation(10).

Next, and in contrast with this linear impact of risk aversion, the im- pact of the attitude towards ambiguity is not so direct. Indeed, for an ambiguity averse decision maker, the fact that investment in the risky asset is increasing with the reduction of ambiguity (whencincreases to- wards 1/2, the ambiguity decreases) depends on the value ofλ, the mar- ket price of risk.

Indeed, in the case of ambiguity aversion, if the market price of riskλ is relatively small, the quantity of risky (and ambiguous) asset is also de- creasing with the ambiguity aversion. But if the market price of risk is relatively important, the quantity of risky asset is greater than in the ab- sence of ambiguity and, furthermore, increasing with the ambiguity aversion. In this case, there is some trade-off between risk and ambiguity.

Finally, models where ambiguity has only one type of effect may be somewhat restrictive. The results of the various applications of ChoquetBrownian ambiguity differ from those of the recursive multiple-priors model of ambiguity to real options (Nishimura and Osaki, 2007) and to the continuous-time capital asset pricing model (Chen and Epstein, 2002). The effect of ambiguity is not straightforward, as reected in the deformations of both the mean and the variance in our Choquet expectations model.

5. Conclusion

In summary, we have shown that with a less-restrictive model than the multiple-priors model, and even in the case of ambiguity aversion (c b1/2), the effects of ambiguity on optimal decisions may vary. We thereby contribute to a growing body of literature focusing on the am- biguity that characterises uncertain prospects.

Expanding economic andnancial models to incorporate the many substantial sources of uncertainty that characterise them remains chal- lenging, in spite of signicant breakthroughs in the decision sciences over the last two decades. Even if a typical investor may often be de- scribed as conservative and cautious, ambiguity-seeking is also a reality.

Adopting ChoquetBrownian ambiguity avoids an early reduction of the range of possible preferences regarding ambiguity. This may be an

(7)

interesting feature in contexts where aversion may not be the only ac- ceptable attitude toward ambiguity.

In addition to the applications presented inSection 4to portfolio choice, real options theory and environmental policy, our approach has possible applications to any model in which ambiguity is present, for example, to macroeconomicuncertainty models,where central banks do not know thetrueeconomic model. Expansion of prefer- ences to a wider range of preferences also opens the way for applica- tions to entrepreneurial models or to the study of contractual arrangements under ambiguity. To conclude, ChoquetBrownian ambi- guity can be applied to a rich range of issues where beliefs cannot be represented by standard probability measures. ChoquetBrownian am- biguity may thus usefully complement other models of utility in sto- chastic continuous-time settings.

Acknowledgments

The authors especially wish to thank participants at the Foundations of Utility, Risk and Decision Theory (FUR) International Conferences and at the World Risk and Insurance Economics Conference (WRIEC) for their useful comments and suggestions.

Appendix 1. Axiomatic basis for Choquet random walks

In this appendix, we establish the key axioms and properties of Choquet random walks (for a more extensive presentation please refer toKast and Lapied, 2010a). Suppose a decision maker is aware of its preferences over payoffs contingent on uncertain states, i.e., measur- able functions fromStoR. These preferences may satisfyDieccidue and Wakker (2002)axioms and be represented by a value function on the set of uncertain payoffs:

Axiom 1.Preferences dene acomplete pre-orderon the set of measur- able functions.

Axiom 2.For any measurable functionX, there exists a constant num- ber (constant equivalent), for which the decision maker is indifferent to the function, i.e.,

XE Xð Þðwhererepresents indifferenceÞ:

Axiom 3. Preferences allow no comonotonic Dutch Books.

A comonotonic Dutch Book is anite sequence of random variable pairsfi,giwith thefis and thegis in a comonotonic set and such that: i;figiandsS;

i

fið Þsb∑

i

gið Þ.s 1.1. Interpretation

At eachstep,XXbut at the end of all steps the result is actually the following:XX. Mimicking the case of standard Dutch books, after a series ofsuccessivebets, the DM is losing in all possible situations.

Then, according toDieccidue and Wakker (2002):For a preference relation on RSsatisfyingAxioms 1 and 2, for allXinRS, there exists a con- stant equivalentE(X)R, such that the following three statements are equivalent:

(i) E(.):RSRare strictly monotonic, additive on comonotonic vectors (but not necessarily additive on non-comonotonic vectors).

(ii) There exists a unique capacity such thatE(X) is the Choquet inte- gral of X with respect to this measure.

(iii) E(.) is such thatAxiom 3is satised.

Otherwise stated: v, a unique capacity on (S, 2S), XtE Xt

ð Þ ¼

S

Xtdν:

Let us note that, in this representation theorem, the (subjective) ca- pacity aggregates all the decision maker's behaviour: there is no need for utility on payoffs, and the certainty equivalent is merely an expected (subjective) value. Similarly, a decision maker has preferences for pres- ent over future consumption (payoffs, here), i.e., preferences over pay- offs are contingent on dates. We assume that the decision maker's preferences over certain future payoffs satisfyKoopman's (1972)ax- ioms and are represented by a linear function.

Axiom 4. Preferences dene a complete continuous pre-order on the set of measurable functions. Preferences are also strictly monotonic and satisfy separability over dates.

Then, according toKoopman's theorem (1972):

For a preference relation on RTsatisfyingAxioms4for all X in RT, there exists a present equivalent D(X)R such that:∃π, a unique bounded addi- tive measure on (T, 2T), XsD Xð Þ ¼s

T

Xsdπ. Or in terms of preferences:

Axiom 5. Dynamic consistency axiom

t= 1,,T1,X,Xsuch that:

Xτð Þ ¼s Xτð Þs;∀τ¼0;…;t;sS; itIt;X≈i

t

X

XX:

Let us clarify the relation between our approach and papers where a weakened axiom of dynamic consistency and of model consistency is considered (e.gKarni and Schmeidler, 1991; Sarin and Waker, 1998).

On the one hand, Sarin and Wakker express dynamic consistency to- gether with the compound lotteries axiom: The valuation of a two-stage lottery and the valuation of the equivalent one-stage lottery is the same.

They also add model consistency (namedsequential consistency).

On the other hand, for KarniSchmeidler dynamic consistency is the preservation of preferences between therst period and second period, when the counterfactual payoffs are the same for the two lotteries.

In contrast, our expression of dynamic consistency is the same as in Nishimura and Ozaki (2003): when a lottery is preferred to another at therst stage,for any possible information set, then, it is preferred at the second stage.

Consequently our hypothesis is not weaker nor stronger than Karni and Schmeidler's hypothesis: it is not weaker because the set of lotteries considered by Karni and Schmeidler (with identical counterfactual pay- offs) is included in the set of lotteries we consider. It is not stronger be- cause there is not equivalence between the preferences at period one and period two, but an implication from period one to period two.

Axiom 6. Model consistency axiom

Preferences conditional on information satisfyAxioms 13and the hierarchy axiom between time and uncertainty.

If the criterions for time and/or uncertainty are not linear, the discounted expectation (DE) and the expected discounting (ED) are not equivalent. Here, discounting is linear and not expectation (Choquet expectation). In this case, the appropriate method is DE (Cf.Kast and Lapied, 2010b).13

We can now state the following condition expressing consistency between conditional and unconditional expectations.

13 The Hierarchy axiom between time and uncertainty may be expressed as such: pref- erences of the decision maker over payoffs contingent onΩ=S×T, are represented by V=DE. The subjective product measureυ×πonS×Tcaptures the decision maker's be- haviour both on uncertainty and on time.

Références

Documents relatifs

We focus on the existence and characterization of the limit for a certain critical branching random walks in time–space random environment in one dimension which was introduced

Collected in this section are several estimates for simple random walks on graphs, which are used in proving the convergence of the local times of jump processes on finite trees

(5.9) pour toute suite de mesures positives p,n sur l'ensemble fini En vérifiant la condition la condition projective f^f^n-\-i = l^n pour tout n, il existe une mesure positive

Then Bro\vnian motion is transient on M if and only if the admissible (with respect to the induced metric ) random walks on T that are symmetric with respect to {X,=Vol

A change in the level of perceived ambiguity has an impact on project value as well as on reservation value, consequently impacting the timing of exercise of real options with

A change in the level of perceived ambiguity has an impact on project value as well as on reservation value, consequently impacting the timing of exercise of real options with

2 In correlated random walk, the direction chosen at step i+1 may be related to the direction of step i (a phenomenon termed ‘persistence’, since Patlak 1953). 3 Capacities are a

This description is not as complete as the corresponding one for finite energy classes in [GZ07]; Choquet classes are rather meant to become a useful intermediate tool in the