• Aucun résultat trouvé

A note on choosing the alternative with the best median evaluation

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "A note on choosing the alternative with the best median evaluation"

Copied!
15
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-00397403

https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00397403v2

Preprint submitted on 5 Jul 2010

HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires

A note on choosing the alternative with the best median evaluation

Jean-François Laslier

To cite this version:

Jean-François Laslier. A note on choosing the alternative with the best median evaluation. 2010.

�hal-00397403v2�

(2)

A NOTE ON CHOOSING THE ALTERNATIVE WITH THE BEST MEDIAN EVALUATION

Jean-François LASLIER

Cahier n° 2010-17

ECOLE POLYTECHNIQUE

CENTRE NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE

DEPARTEMENT D'ECONOMIE

Route de Saclay 91128 PALAISEAU CEDEX

(33) 1 69333033

http://www.economie.polytechnique.edu/

mailto:chantal.poujouly@polytechnique.edu

(3)

A note on choosing the alternative with the best median evaluation

Jean-François Laslier

Département d’Économie, École Polytechnique 91128 Palaiseau, France

Jean-Francois.Laslier@polytechnique.edu First version May 2009, this version June 2010.

Abstract

The voting rule proposed by Basset and Persky (Public Choice 99: 299- 310) picks the alternative with best median evaluation. The present note shows that this MaxMed principle is equivalent to ask the social planner to apply the MaxMin principle allowing him to discard half of the population.

In one-dimensional, single-peaked domains, the paper compares this rule with majority rule and the utilitarian criterion. The MaxMed outcome is rejected by a majority of voters in favor of outcomes which are also utilitarian improvements.

1 Introduction

When di¤erent individuals evaluate one object on some common scale, taking as a summary of the various evaluations their median is a natural idea, often used in Statistics. Using this idea for collective choice among several alternative objects is thus occasionally proposed: the suggestion is that an alternative with the largest median evaluation is to be chosen. I will call this method the MaxMed voting scheme.

In the modern literature this was (up to my knowledge) proposed by Basset

and Persky, 1999 [2]. Properties of the best median can be expressed in the

language of utility theory (Bossert and Weymark 2004 [3]): the informational

basis is the ordinal and inter-individuallly comparable framework. In terms

of utilities, the utility levels attached by the di¤erent individuals to a given

alternative are compared (inter-individual comparability), and the median is

stable under any strictly increasing transformation of utility provided that the

transformation is the same for all individuals (ordinality). This is the same

informational basis as for the MaxMin, or Rawls principle. As will be shown,

instead of maximizing the satisfaction of the least favored individual in the

whole society, as the MaxMin does, MaxMed maximizes the satisfaction of the

least favored individual when half of the population can be discarded.

(4)

As to strategic aspects, supporters of this method claim that it is relatively immune to individual misrepresentation of evaluations. The reason for this claim is that the median (contrary to the mean) is “robust” in the statistical sense.

For instance, in most cases, over-evaluating an object in order to push up its median has simply no consequence. This argument was put forward by Basset and Persky [2], who used the term “Robust Voting” to describe this method.

But, in fact, voting rules generally share the property that one voter is rarely pivotal so that, in practice, median voting does not appear to be less, nor more, manipulable than other voting rules (Gerhlein and Lepelley 2003 [6]).

Some properties of the MaxMed method are collected by Warren Smith at the Center for Range Voting [10]. Using a limited set of grades, several candi- dates usually end up with the same grade. Balinski and Laraki, 2007 [1] have proposed several, more or less complicated, ways to choose among them, and have ellaborated on the question of robustness to manipulation. Felsenthal and Machover, 2008 [4] is a discussion of these issues.

In this paper I will leave aside the strategic questions and assume that voters vote sincerely. I also leave aside the problem of ties associated with the use of MaxMed voting in practice, by assuming that an evaluation can be any real number. I will attempt to compare the outcomes of di¤erent choice principles, including MaxMed, in a setting which is standard in Economic and Political Theory and is relevant for the applications. I consider one-dimensional, single- peaked utility pro…les with distributions of voters’ideal points which are skewed (without loss of generality: skewed to the left).

From the point of view of Social Choice Theory, one-dimensional, single peaked pro…les are very speci…c pro…les because they avoid Condorcet cycles, but they nevertheless constitute an interesting benchmark case. In Political Economy, this assumption is so common that it is often not even mentioned.

The idea that the distribution of voters with respect to the relevant parameter is not uniform or symmetric but skewed is an empirical observation: it seems to be a general rule that socioeconomic relevant parameters are “skewed to the left,” the paradigmatic example being income distributions: most people earn less than the average.

In this setting, Condorcet-consistent voting rules are very simple, and all alike: all of them chose the median of the voters’ideal points, which is a Con- dorcet winner in virtue of the celebrated Median Voter Theorem. This is the outcome of majority voting. By comparison, the utilitarian choice (the e¢ cient alternative in the sense of maximizing the sum of individual utilities, I will call it the Bentham winner) tends, in the same setting, to produce choice which are favored by richer people. Although this observation is not as clear-cut as the Median Voter Theorem is, it matches the economic intuition and can be stated formally if one makes the (standard) assumption of quadratic utility. In that case the utilitarian optimum is simply the mean of the distribution of ideal points. For left-skewed distribution, the mean is larger than the median.

Then, where is the alternative with the best median evaluation located? Is

it close to the utilitarian optimum or not, and if not, in which direction does it

diverges from the optimum: to the left, in the direction of the ideal points of

(5)

the majority, or to the right, in the direction of the rich minority? How does it compare to the outcome of Majority rule, the Condorcet winner? Is it more or less e¢ cient than this outcome?

In order to answer this question, I present one very simple analytical exam- ple, plus computer simulations under various hypothesis which will be described in the sequel. The reached conclusion is always the same: the best median is located on the wrong side of the Condorcet winner. The Bentham-inne¢ ciency of the best median choice is of the same kind but worse than the Bentham- inne¢ ciency of majority voting.

The example maybe useful in order to understand what one does when com- paring medians. The usual argument for rejecting an alternative A in favor of another alternative B when a majority of individuals prefer A to B is that members of the relatively small population who gain in this move gain a lot while members of the losing majority incur a relatively small loss. This is a typ- ical Benthamite, utilitarian argument. Conversely, the Bentham-inne¢ ciency of majority voting derives from the democratic power of the (many) poor

1

. This ine¢ ciency can be justi…ed by normative political arguments in favor of the prin- ciple of majority rule. It can also often be justi…ed by invoking the argument of decreasing individual marginal utility. In the one-dimensional settings under scrutiny, the best median choice goes further away from e¢ ciency, for reasons that are easily understood from the mathematical point of view (the example in section 5 will explain this point) but which have no normative or political appeal: apply Rawls principle to the most homogeneous half-population, with no regard for the other half.

2 Interpretation of the MaxMed

In order to explain what one does when chosing the alternative with the best possible median evaluation, it is useful to introduce some de…nitions and pieces of notation.

De…nition 1 Consider a population P of individuals and a set X of alterna- tives. The Rawlsian evaluation of x 2 X by P is:

R(P; x) = min

i2P

u

i

(x) and the Rawlsian satisfaction of P is:

R(P ) = max

x2X

R(P; x):

Notice that this vocabulary may not be exactly true to John Rawls’ ideas (Rawls 1971 [8]), but it is customary in Economics to call Rawls’principle the idea of giving full priority to the worst-o¤ individuals (Kolm 1972 [7], Fleurbaey and Hammond 2004 [5]).

1

At the limit one can wonder why, under majority rule, “the poor do not expropriate the

rich”; see Roemer, 1998 [9].

(6)

De…nition 2 Let I, with measure 1, be the (in…nite) set of inviduals and let H be the set of all sub-populations of measure 1=2. Suppose that, for an alternative x, the evaluation u

i

(x) of x by i is continuously distributed in I. Then we denote by med

i2I

u

i

(x) the median evaluation of x, uniquely de…ned by the fact that for some half-population H 2 H ,

u

j

(x) med

i2I

u

i

(x) u

h

(x) for all h 2 H and all j 2 I n H .

Notice that for a …nite population, if the number of individual is odd then there are no subpopulation of measure 1=2, and that if the number of individuals is odd then the median is generally not unique For simplicity I consider from now an in…nite population in which the median evaluation of each alternative is well de…ned, and I shall indicate how the …ndings extend to the …nite case.

Let x

MaxMed

be an alternative with the largest median evaluation and let u

MaxMed

be this evaluation. By de…nition those are obtained by the following algorithm:

1. For each alternative x 2 X, compute u

med

(x) = med

i

u

i

(x) the median of the evaluations of x by all individuals.

2. Find the largest of these numbers u

MaxMed

= max

x

u

med

(x) and an associ- ated alternative x

MaxMed

which achieves this maximum.

The next lemma will show that the following de…nition is equivalent:

1. For each half-population H of P , compute its Rawlsian satisfaction R(H ).

2. Find the largest of these numbers u

MaxMed

= max

H

R(H ) and an associated alternative x

MaxMed

which achieves this maximum.

Lemma 1

max

x2X

med

i2I

u

i

(x) = max

H2H

R(H )

Proof. Write u = max

x2X

med

i2I

u

i

(x) and r = max

H2H

R(H). To see that u r , take any x 2 X . By de…nition of the median there exists a half-population H 2 H such that 8 j 2 H, med

i2I

u

i

(x) u

j

(x). For this H , R(H; x) = min

j2H

u

j

(x) med

i2I

u

i

(x), which implies that R(H ) med

i2I

u

i

(x). Thus r med

i2I

u

i

(x), hence r u .

Conversely, suppose u > r . Then there exists " > 0 and there exists x 2 X such that med

i2I

u

i

(x) > r + ". For that x:

8 H 2 H ; med

i2I

u

i

(x) > R(H) + ":

By de…nition of the median there exists H

0

such that u

h

(x) med

i2I

u

i

(x) for all h 2 H

0

, hence, for this H

0

, u

h

(x) > R(H

0

) + ". But R(H

0

) = max

y2X

R(H

0

; y) thus, for y = x, we have that

8 h 2 H

0

; u

h

> R(H

0

; x) + ":

(7)

Taking the min on h, one obtains the contradiction R(H

0

; x) R(H

0

; x) +

": Q.E.D.

For a …nite population of odd size n, the same result holds when considering for H the subpopulations of size (n + 1)=2. Here is, for illustration, a simple example with three voters and two alternatives:

u

i

(x) i = 1 i = 2 i = 3 med

i

u

i

(x)

x = a 6 7 8 7

x = b 4 3 9 4

Table 1: best median evaluation.

R(H; x) H = f 1; 2 g H = f 1; 3 g H = f 2; 3 g

x = a 6 6 7

x = b 3 4 3

R(H ) 6 6 7

Table 2: Most favored half population

3 The one-dimensional model

The set of available alternatives is the set of positive real numbers X = [0; + 1 [.

To each individual i is attached an ideal point x

i

2 X . The utility of i for an alternative y 2 X is denoted u

i

(y). Under the quadratic utility assumption one has:

u

i

(y) = (y x

i

)

2

: (Variants of this assumption will be considered later.)

The society is then described by the distribution of ideal points. Let F denotes the cumulative distribution: for any x 2 X, F (x) is the proportion of individuals i such that x

i

< x. We suppose that F is continuous and has a mean.

The Condorcet winner is then well-de…ned and unique, it is the median of the distribution, that is the alternative, denoted x

Cond

such that:

F (x

Cond

) = 1=2:

The alternative which maximizes the total utility W (y) = R

X

(y x)

2

dF (x) is the average of the ideal points. We call this point the Bentham optimum and denote it by x

Bentham

:

x

Bentham

= Z

x

x dF(x):

For any alternative y, the utility levels obtained by the various individuals

induce a probability distribution that we denote by E

y

: for any utility level

u 0, E

y

(u) is the proportion of individuals in the society whose utility for

(8)

y is less than u. Given our assumption about utilities, these individuals are precisely those whose ideal points are at a distance larger than p

u from y:

u

i

(y) < u () (y x

i

)

2

< u () x

i

2 = y p

u; y + p u thus

E

y

(u) = 1 F (y + p

u) + F(y p u)

and the median evaluation of y, denoted u

med

(y) is such that E

y

(u

med

(y)) = 1=2, that is:

F(y + p

u

med

(y)) F (y p

u

med

(y)) = 1=2:

It may be more convenient to write this formula with d(y) = p

u

med

(y) as:

Z

y+d(y) y d(y)

dF (x) = 1=2:

The best median evaluation choice, the outcome of “median evaluation”

is denoted by x

MaxMed

, its is the point which maximizes u

med

or, equivalently, which minimize d. In general it is di¢ cult to compute this point, but the example in the next sections makes these computations very simple.

4 Two results for non-symetric distributions

Here we consider the case of continuous distribution of ideal points with a density that is continuous and monotonous on its support. Without loss of generality we take the density to be decreasing and the support to be S = [0; b] or S = [0; + 1 ).

Theorem 1 Suppose that the distribution F of voters’ ideal points has a con- tinuous density f on its support S and that f is decreasing on S. Suppose that voters have quadratic utilities u

i

(y) = (y x

i

)

2

. Then x

Bentham

x

Cond

. Proof. The fact that x

Bentham

x

Cond

is just the fact that, for such a dis- tribution, the average is larger than the median. For a proof, consider G the distribution made of a mass m at 0 plus a uniform distribution on [0; c].

Routine computation shows that, for G, the median is smaller than the av- erage. Take G(x) =

12

+ (x x

Cond

) f(x

Cond

), c = x

Cond

+

2f(x1

Cond)

and m = 1=2 x

Cond

f (x

Cond

). The median of G is x

Cond

. The cumulative func- tion G is above F so F stochastically dominates G and thus the average of F is larger than the average of G. Therefore the average of F is larger than its

median. Q.E.D.

(9)

Theorem 2 Suppose that the distribution F of voters’ideal points has a contin- uous density f on its support S and that f is decreasing on S. Suppose that vot- ers have utilities ordinally equivalent to quadratic utilities u

i

(y) = (y x

i

)

2

for strictly increasing. Then x

MaxMed

=

12

x

Cond

.

Proof. Note that for any population P with support [y; y + 2d], the Rawlsian satisfaction is obtained for the choice y + d and has value R(P ) = ( d

2

=4).

Therefore, in view of Lemma 1, x

MaxMed

is the value of y + d that minimizes d under the constraint that Z

y+2d

y

dF = 1=2

for some y 0. This constraint can be written as F (y + 2d) = 1=2 + F (y) or, equivalently:

d = (1=2)F

1

(1=2 + F(y)) (y):

Given our hypotheses, the function ( ) is diferentiable for y 0, and 2

0

(y) = f (y)

f (y + 2 (y)) 1:

Because f is decreasing, the ratio in this expression is smaller than 1, thus is decreasing too, and is maximized for the smallest value y = 0. It follows that F(2d) = 1=2, which means that x

Cond

= 2d. Hence the result. Q.E.D.

5 A simple example

Suppose that the distribution of voters’ideal point has bounded support [0; 1]

with an a¢ ne density function parametrized by a skewness parameter , with 0 < 1:

f (t) = 1 + 2 t:

For = 0 the density is uniform on [0; 1] and for > 0 the density is skewed on the left. For = 1 the density is triangular. Figure 1 is drawn for = 1=3.

Then for 0 x 1, F (x) =

Z

x 0

(1 + 2 t) dt = (1 + )x x

2

:

Majority Voting: Condorcet winner. See point C in Figure 1. The median of the ideal points is such that F (x

Cond

) = 1=2, that is 2 x

2

2(1 + )x + 1 = 0, which gives:

x

Cond

= 1

2 1 + p

1 +

2

:

(10)

x

Bentham

x

Cond

x

MaxMed

0 1=2 1=2 1=4

= 1=2 :42 :38 :19

= 1 :33 :29 :15

Table 1: Choices for an a¢ ne distribution with skewness

Some values are provided in Table 1. When the skewness tends to 0, x

Cond

tends to 1=2.

Utilitarian evaluation: Bentham optimum. See point B in Figure 1. The average of the ideal points is x

Bentham

= R

2

0

tf (t)dt and computation shows:

x

Bentham

= 1 2 6 :

Again, when the skewness tends to 0, x

Bentham

tends to 1=2, like x

Cond

. Maximal Median evaluation: See point M in Figure 1. In order to compute the median evaluation at a point y one has to …nd a radius d(y) such that half of the ideal points are located in the segment [y d(y); y + d(y)], and half are located outside. The best median is then obtained at the point y such that d(y) is the smallest. In Figure 1, one can see that the best median is precisely the mid-point between 0 and the Condorcet winner x

Cond

. Indeed, by de…nition of x

Cond

, half of the population belongs to the segment [0; x

Cond

], and because the density is decreasing, any other segment of length smaller or equal will contain strictly less than half of the population. Therefore:

x

MaxMed

= x

Cond

2 = 1

4 1 + p

1 +

2

:

When the skewness tends to 0, x

MaxMed

tends to 1=4, unlike the two other choices.

One can see on this simple example the result announced in the introduction:

Proposition 1 For any a¢ ne distribution f of skewness > 0:

x

MaxMed

< x

Cond

< x

Bentham

:

Proof. This follows from the theorems above, but a direct proof is easy: For any 2 (0; 1], the inequality

21

1 + p

1 +

2

<

12 6

is shown algebraically by letting u = p

1 +

2

, and the result follows. Q.E.D.

Notice that the phenomenon, which holds for any value of the skewness

parameter , is all the most striking for very small vallues of , which coresponds

to distributions which are almost not skewed. In that case, letting tend to 0, the

(11)

B

0 M C 1

Figure 1: Three choices from a skewed distribution of ideal points

Condorcet winner and the utilitarian optimum both tend to 1=2, the center of the distribution: for almost symmetric distributions, there is no con‡ict between the utilitarian and the majoritarian principles: both chose a consensual outcome in the middle of the distribution. But things are totally di¤erent with MaxMed, whose choice tends to 1=4. As we have seen this choice is due to the fact that the MaxMed calculus allows to leave aside half of the population.

The graphical representation makes transparent the explanation of the phe-

nomenon. Half of the population lies on each side of the Condorcet winner

x

Cond

= C, but the right side (between C and 1) is wider than the left one (be-

tween 0 and C). This should be an argument in favor of a collective choice larger

than C, like the utilitarian optimum x

Bentham

= B, because individuals at the

left of C are relatively close to C while those at the right of C are relatively far

from C. This is a typical utilitarian argument, that weights numbers of individ-

uals and intensity of preferences. The reasoning of the MaxMed argument, that

leads to the choice x

MaxMed

= M , is reversed: the window being narrower on

the left and wider on the right, chosing a point in the middle of the left window

will satisfy the left half of the population and will reach for the — already quite

satis…ed — members of this group a relatively high level of satisfaction because

this group is not too diverse. On the contrary, choosing a point on the right of

M , such as C or B, the satis…ed half of the population would be spread over a

larger segment and it will be more di¢ cult to reach the same level of satisfaction

for this half population, because these people are more diverse.

(12)

- 1 1 2 3 4 5 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6

Figure 2: Log-Normal distribution

The choice of M is dictated by the level of satisfaction obtained by some half of the population. By de…nition of the MaxMed, this level is the largest than can be obtained by any half of the population, thanks to inter-individual comparability. But, doing so, it neglects the (maybe very low) level of satisfac- tion obtained by the other half of the population, thanks to ordinality. There is no compromise here: …nd the half of the population which would be better o¤ if they were in power ! This “majoritarian” logic is ‡awed, as one can see on the example, because the result is that moves away from M in the direction of the center simultaneously (i) satisfy the majority criterion: more losers than winners, and (ii) satisfy the utilitarian criterion: the losers loose less than what the winners win.

6 Simulated examples with Log-Normal distri- bution

In the simulations, I compute the Bentham optimum, the outcome of Majority Rule (the Concorcet winner), the outcome of the Borda rule (the Borda winner) and the point with the best median evaluation. I work with a Log-Normal distri- bution, which is typically the kind of distribution met in Social Sciences (Figure 2) rather than a¢ ne distributions as in the previous section. The theoretical mean of the Log-Normal distribution of parameters 0 and 1 is 1:649 and the stan- dard deviation is 2:161. The distribution vanishes quickly after x = 5 and, when needed, I restrict attention to the segment [0; 5].

2

I pick at random 999 ideal points according to this distribution. Then, in a …rst example, the individual

2

This has no impact on the value of the Condorcet winner nor on the MaxMed. It leads to

a slight underestimation of the Bentham optimum and the Borda winner.

(13)

candidates n

k

u

i

(y) Bentham Borda Condorcet MV

d

2

2 1 1 :5

11 d 1 1 1 :5

uniform d

1=2

1 1 1 :5

d

2

1:77 1:15 1:04 :62

49 d 1:04 1:15 1:04 :62

d

1=2

:83 1:15 1:04 :62

d

2

1:68 :92 :92 :56

11 d :92 :92 :92 :56

repres. d

1=2

:83 :92 :92 :56

d

2

1:89 :93 1:04 :56

49 d 1:04 :93 1:04 :56

d

1=2

:85 :93 1:04 :56

Table 2: Various speci…cations and choices with a Log-Normal Distribution

utility functions are quadratic: u

i

(y) = (y x

i

)

2

, and there are 11 candidates evenly spread between 0 and 5 (at points 0, :5, 1, 1:5, 2; 2:5, :::, 5). In that case, the Bentham optimum is located at x

Bentham

= 2, the Borda winner and the Condorcet winner are both located at x

Cond

= x

Borda

= 1, and the best median evaluation is obtained at 0:5, thus: x

MaxMed

< x

Cond

= x

Borda

< x

Bentham

An alternative speci…cation is that the utility is decreasing linearly with the distance: u

i

(y) = j y x

i

j . I label this case linear utility. Going from one speci…cation to the other does not change the Condorcet or Borda winner nor does it change the median evaluations, because this is a strictly increasing trans- formation common to all individuals. But it changes the utilitarian optimum, which is now equal to the Condorcet winner. (Recall that the solution to the problem min

y

P

i

j y x

i

j is the median of the x

i

s.): Thus in that case, one has:

x

MaxMed

< x

Cond

= x

Borda

= x

Bentham

.

Although economists usually work with concave utility functions (used as VNM utilities, these function are risk-adverse), it also makes sense in Politics to consider that the marginal utility is decreasing with the distance to the ideal point and to use utilities of the form u

i

(y) = p

j y x

i

j . We label this case root utility. In the example, simulation shows: x

MaxMed

< x

Cond

= x

Borda

= x

Bentham

.

Table 2 reports the results of simulations in various cases. Quadratic utility is used for the lines labelled d

2

, linear utility for the lines d, and root utility for the lines d

1=2

. The number of candidates, n

k

, is 11 or 49. Candidates are either evenly spaced from 0 to 5 (“uniform” case), or chosen according to the same probability distribution of the voters (“representative” case).

The simulations reported in Table 2 are not averaged. Randomness comes from the choice of the 999 individual ideal points and (in the “representative”

setting) of the choice of the candidate positions. This last point is important

for n

k

= 11. In order to check the robustness of the results I replicated some

of the above experiences. For instance here are the results obtained during 100

(14)

(100 simulations) Bentham Borda Condorcet MV

mean value 1.56 .87 1.01 .65

standard deviation .28 .17 .13 .12

Table 3: Robustness of the results for 11 representative candidates and quadratic utility

(100 simulations) Bentham-Condor Condor-Borda Borda-MV

mean value .55 .14 .22

standard deviation .29 .22 .19

Table 4: Robustness of the results for 11 representative candidates and quadratic utility

simulations for the representative case with n

k

= 11 candidates and quadratic utilities.

Out of 100 simulations, the usual ranking is: x

MaxMed

< x

Borda

x

Cond

<

x

Bentham

. More exactly:

the strict inequality x

MaxMed

< x

Borda

occurs 82 times, x

MaxMed

= x

Cond

occurs 17 times, and x

MaxMed

> x

Cond

occurs only once;

the strict inequality x

Borda

< x

Cond

occurs 50 times, x

Borda

= x

Cond

occurs 46 times, and x

Borda

> x

Cond

occurs 4 times;

the strict inequality x

Cond

< x

Bentham

occurs 95 times, x

Cond

= x

D

occurs 5 times, and x

Cond

> x

Bentham

does not occur.

Tables 3 and 4 provide further details about this robustness analysis. In

this model, Borda and Condorcet are not well distinguished, but the ranking

x

MaxMed

< x

Cond

< x

Bentham

appears to be robust. This indicates that the

observations that were made in the analytical sections are robust.

(15)

References

[1] Balinski, M. and R. Laraki (2007) “A theory of measuring, electing, and ranking” PNAS, 104, 8720–8725.

[2] Basset, G.W. and J. Persky (1999) “Robust Voting” Public Choice 99:

299-310.

[3] Bossert, W. and J. Weymark (2004) “Utility in social choice”pp.1099-1177 in S. Barbera, P. Hammond and C. Seidl (eds.) Handbook of Utility Theory, Volume 2 Boston: Kluwer.

[4] Felsenthal, D. and M. Machover (2008) “The Majority Judgment Voting Procedure: A Critical Evaluation” Homo Oeconomicus 25 (3/4).

[5] Fleurbaey, M. and P. Hammond (2004) “Interpersonally comparable util- ity”pp.1179-1285 in S. Barbera, P. Hammond a,d C. Seidl (eds.) Handbook of Uttility Theory, Volume 2 Boston: Kluwer.

[6] Gehrlein, W. V. and D. Lepelley (2003) “On some limitations of the median voting rule” Public Choice 117: 177-190.

[7] Kolm, S. (1972) Justice et équité. Paris: Editions du CNRS.

[8] Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univer- sity Press.

[9] Roemer, J. (1998) “Why the Poor do not Expropriate the Rich: An Old Argument in New Garb” Journal of Public Economics 70, 399-424.

[10] Range Voting http://rangevoting.org/MedianVrange.html.

Références

Documents relatifs

lation of the required preferential independence hypothesis. Consider, however, two certainly preferentially independent selection criteria: Cost and Space in a car selection

Prevalence of anxiety and depression among medical and pharmaceutical students in Alexandria University. Alexandria Journal of Medicine Volume 51, Issue 2 , June 2015,

Neumann or Robin boundary conditions â First results with a mixed formulation Dynamic equation : heat equation. Michel Duprez Rule of the mesh in the Finite Element

В разделе 5 рассматриваются алгоритмы решения постав- ленной задачи: вспомогательный алгоритм определения существования маршрутов из каж- дого узла множества

By considering religion and nationalism as sociohistorical imaginaries, religion and nationalism are conceived as forms relative to the paradigmatic

In its standard form, a European-style call on the maximum (the “best”) of n assets provides the investor, at the option expiry, with the difference, if positive, between the highest

Drs Philip Bock and Brian Milligan, Dalhousie University Dr Keith Short, Memorial University of Newfoundland These awards recognize the best scholarly work of senior family

We have been told that our residents perform the best on the American Board of Family Medicine examinations—bet- ter than American-trained family