• Aucun résultat trouvé

View of Contemplation as a Corrective to Technological Education

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Partager "View of Contemplation as a Corrective to Technological Education"

Copied!
23
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

Canadian Journal of Education / Revue canadienne de l’éducation 36:3 (2013)

©2013 Canadian Society for the Study of Education/

Sean Steel University of Calgary

Abstract

This paper argues that noetic studies, contemplation, or theoria ought to take greater pre- cedence in education than is currently the case. Our modern focus on and fascination with information technologies serves in many ways to thwart and to discourage the cultivation of noetic studies and the pursuit of wisdom in schools. The suggestion throughout this paper is that if the significance of pre-modern and non-technological ways of knowing could be made clear and convincing to education stakeholders, it seems likely that the appropriateness of such pursuits might be recognized, and their practice rendered more frequent as a kind of corrective to technological education.

Keywords: technology, ancient philosophy, contemplative studies, education

Precis

Cet article soutient que les études en « sciences noétiques, » la méditation ou la con- templation devraient actuellement occuper une plus grande place qu’elles ne le font en matière d’éducation. Aujourd’hui, notre fascination pour les technologies de l’in- formation, et l’importance qu’on y accorde, sert à bien des égards à contrecarrer et à

(2)

décourager la culture des études en sciences noétiques et la quête de la sagesse dans les écoles. Cet article s’applique à démontrer, que si l’importance des moyens pré-modernes et non technologiques liés au savoir pouvait être rendue claire et convaincante aux yeux des responsables des politiques éducatives, il semble probable que la pertinence de telles activités pourrait être reconnue, et leur pratique rendue plus fréquente, constituant une sorte de « correction » à l’enseignement technologique.

(3)

Introduction:

A Recollection of Pre-Technological Ways of Knowing

Today, we often use the word contemplation to name any sort of deep thinking. How- ever, the ancient roots of this word are rich with a specific meaning that has largely been forgotten and that merits recollection. It is correct to suppose that contemplation (Lt.

contemplatio; Gk. theoria) names a kind of cognitive activity; however, the ancient sense of this word must be distinguished from critical-analytic reasoning (ratio) that is the mainstay of our modern educational efforts. Rather than describing the laborious cogni- tive activity of a thinking subject standing over against its object (Lt. ob-iectum, mean- ing “thrown against”) as it moves from point to point in a line of reasoning, the ancient sense of contemplation refers to direct, non-linear knowing; it involves not separation but rather the union of knower with what is known in the act of seeing (theoria); not through the discursiveness of ratio but in the immediate apprehension of intellectus does the loving gaze of contemplation unify seer with what is seen. And where the discursive thought of ratio is indeed a form of work, the passive, receptive gaze of intellectus is not; rather, it is an effortless, immediate grasping of (or perhaps being grasped by) what is seen. Contemplative knowing is therefore always associated not with toil but instead with leisure. Our language still pays lip service to this important relation between con- templation, leisure, and education inasmuch as our word school is derived from the Greek word for leisure (schole). In ancient understanding, intellectus was always esteemed more highly than ratio as the mode of our perfection in genuine happiness (Gk. euda- imonia; Lt. beatitudo). Aristotle uses the word immortalization (to athanatizein, 2001, Nicomachean Ethics, X.vii.8) to describe the activity of the intellectus in relation to what is perfect or best (the Ariston); today, however, the significance of the intellectus and its contemplative activity has been drastically diminished (if not entirely forgotten) in favour of exclusive attention to the discursive skills of the ratio—a fact not lost on contempor- ary contemplative writers on education like Laurence Freeman (Freeman, 2012, p. 5).

Responding to this need, educators like Charles and Patricia Posnett advocate for the incorporation of simple contemplative activities within the school days of elementary children (Posnett, 2013).

Where Latin authors used the terms ratio and intellectus to distinguish the dis- cursive power of thinking from contemplative cognition, Greek authors spoke in terms

(4)

of dianoia (thought) and noesis (intellection). Dianoetic thought includes the deductive, inductive, and evaluative use of fundamentals or principles (archai) discovered by the mind, whether these underlie mathematics, science, the arts, or stand as the basic cultural presuppositions or “first things” of a culture or community. In any case, dianoia applies these archai downward into the realm of human activity; noesis, by contrast, takes up (anairesis) all such archai towards their true beginning or ground (Arche). In this regard, noesis names that desire of the intellectus not just to see (theorein), but to see what is in its entirety, and to grasp through its gaze the very ground of all that is.

Traditionally, the pursuit of wisdom, or philosophy (Gk. philia-sophia: literally

“the love of wisdom”) has been called the “science of being qua being” (Aristotle, 2001, Metaphysics IV.ii; 1005a.5), or of the things that are (ta onta) due to its character as a noetic activity as opposed to a scientific or dianoetic one. However, the noetic pursuit of wisdom is not the exclusive preserve of philosophers. The vipassana meditation of the Buddhist, the samatha meditation of the yogin, and the contemplative prayer of the Chris- tian or Muslim practitioner all embody the upward movement (anairesis) of the mind towards its ground. Moreover, the activity of the intellectus is not to be conceived of as an elite activity. Plato remarks in his Phaedrus that lovers of beauty (philokalos) relish the noetic movement of the intellectus, as do musical souls (mousikou tinos) or, for that matter, souls of a loving (erotikou) or erotic nature (Plato, 1961, 248d). In short, anytime we come to know what is by loving—that is, when we experience knowing as joy in the appreciation of our union as seers with what is seen—we engage in theoria. There are, in- deed, many such modes of pursuing wisdom and engaging our students in contemplative activities in today’s classroom.

If we are to understand the ancient meaning of contemplation properly, it is im- portant to recognize that noetic and dianoetic activity may never be completely divorced from one another. Rather, the ancients held knowing to be a unity of ratio and intellec- tus—a simultaneous functioning of the two. In today’s schools, where testing and ac- countability structures predominate, however, the dianoetic applications of reason are cul- tivated to the exclusion of noesis. But according to ancient understanding, the exclusively dianoetic machinations of ratio cannot bring about a knowledge of the Highest Good (Summum Bonum) that might enable us to know the true Measure (Metron) of all the oth- er goods we enjoy; even the most adept movements of ratio cannot tell us which innova- tions are good and which are not, nor can they tell us to what end we ought to innovate.

(5)

In other words, the sort of learning that predominates in schools today is insufficient to cultivate wisdom. Without also attending to and cultivating the noetic component of our rationality, we are left with only our own diverse passions and appetites as the means to make decisions about such things.

Reawakening awareness of the intellectus in our pedagogy and incorporating noetic thinking into the classroom need not be considered an onerous or impossible task;

such activity might occur anywhere and at any time. For instance, scientific investigations might, where an openness of spirit is cultivated, give rise to philosophic questions—so too mathematical studies, the investigation of literature and mythology, as well as reflec- tion on our own experiences of love and suffering. Indeed, any sort of basic understand- ing (intellectus) that we have gleaned about anything already presupposes the operations of intellectus, which sees or apprehends the truth. Intellectus is active in the student’s immediate grasp of the axioms (axiomata) and principles (archai) of mathematics and the various sciences. It therefore stands at the beginning (arche) of all our thinking, but it also appears at the end of a line of reasoning when ratio moves us towards yet anoth- er seeing of a truth. Intellectus is active in the student’s witness to beauty, whether that beauty takes a physical or non-physical form; moreover, the joy of intellectus in uniting with its beloved is especially sought out by students in relation to their friends, music, art, dance, or any other pursuit they love for the beauty they find in it.

Since the operation of intellectus is omnipresent in thinking, the challenge of schole is not simply to see (theorein), but to take what one sees upward (anairein) toward its source noetically. Put another way, the challenge of schole is to offer the intellectus evermore-beautiful sights and joyful experiences of beholding the Lovable. The danger for students is not so much that they will not see, but rather that they will suppose that they have already seen everything there is to see—that they will close themselves off to the investigation of what is, that they will refuse to cultivate the broadest and most open form of listening, supposing their own cognition of beauty has already shown them what is truly Beautiful. In short, the danger for students in thinking is for them to suppose that they know what they do not know due to their ignorance or unfamiliarity with higher and better sights worth seeing.

Our current emphasis in schools on being accountable to the predetermined goals and outcomes of the educational system is well known to everyone who has taught in the last twenty years. Our inordinate stress on high-stakes testing and assessment across

(6)

Canada and the United States, with its demand that students demonstrate their knowledge of the correct answers and that they provide evidence of what they know, certainly does little to promote an openness to wonder, a readiness to question, or an eagerness to know the extent of their own ignorance. In fact, our educational system is arguably quite dam- aging noetically inasmuch as it encourages students to beware of demonstrating that they do not know—certainly, they are never to take delight in such a discovery! Yet delight in the discovery that leads one to know thyself (gnothi seauton) is precisely the pleasure associated with the noetic movement towards the highest sights. The dearth of contempla- tive activity (with its associated joys) in today’s schools is well documented in massive studies performed by groups like the Garrison Institute, which have taken great pains to map out the current state of contemplative education in schools (2005). In particular, the Garrison Institute points to the need for the incorporation of contemplative educational activities into our schools as a counterweight to our mainstream concerns with outcomes, assessment, and accountability (2009, p. 2).

How is it, then, that the exercise of intellectus is so ubiquitous, yet so little attend- ed to and largely dismissed in modern education? How is it that our attention in schools has almost completely shifted to the cultivation of the ratio? Why is it that our schools indulge in the discursive work and toil of reason without inviting students to enjoy the leisure of intellection? Most troublesome is the effect that this lopsidedness has had on mass societal consciousness of reality. When all of our knowing becomes a matter of standing over against objects in a position of control, use, and mastery, we cease to see the contemplative or relational aspect of knowing as loving. Our awareness of our own innate ability to gaze upon (theoria) what is and to experience loving union with what is through the contemplative movements of the intellectus fades, yet our craving for this sort of knowing remains. The result of this modern confusion has been that we seek to gratify our desires for such union through the only means of knowing with which we are in any way deeply familiar: namely, the calculative subject-object knowing of the ratio.

Hence, our deepest desires to know take their peculiarly modern form of technological mastery through the adept use and integration of information technologies. What fol- lows in this paper is an exploration of our modern technological confusion. I argue that the solution to our modern day confusions about technology is not evermore education technology, but rather the incorporation of contemplative studies that might, with the relaxation of our focus upon assessment and accountability structures, cultivate noesis throughout the school day.

(7)

On the Deformations of Contemplation in the Allure of Technological Homogeneity

It is incorrect to suppose that theoria, or the immediate seeing of intellectus, is not cur- rently a component of our educational efforts; rather, any time that understanding (intel- lectus) is acquired, the capacity of intellectus for seeing is involved. Buddhist scholar Robert Thurman (2006) makes a similar point when he remarks that the contemplative mind exists in all cultures, and that it can be quite misleading to speak of our own cul- ture as lacking contemplative minds. He explains, “When we make that claim, we are rather lamenting the deplorable contemplative states within which the common mind is absorbed” (p. 1766). Thurman offers television as an example of the sort of contem- plative trance in which millions of people imbibe “for hours on end, day after day, year in and year out” (p. 1766). Unfortunately, he explains, it is a trance “in which sensory dissatisfaction is constantly reinforced, anger and violence is imprinted, and confusion and the delusion of materialism is constructed and maintained” (p. 1766). Hence, “when we talk about seeking to increase and intensify contemplative mind in our culture, we are actually talking about methods of transferring contemplative energies from one focus to another” (p. 1766).

Thurman’s astute observations about television also apply to our current fascina- tion with computers and the Internet—especially in educational circles where the fulfill- ment of ICT outcomes is mandated and strictly enforced both in curriculum documents and as part of Teacher Professional Growth Plans (TPGPs). Teachers are under constant and ever-increasing pressure to bring the latest technologies to bear upon their pedagogy.

The fervour of this pressure becomes all the more peculiar when we recognize that it is doubtful if teachers anywhere have ever experienced similar pressures and threats that they must use television or radio broadcasts (let alone books, paper, pens, and pencils) with their students. Indeed, there seems to be a special kind of seeing that Information Technology (IT) is believed to afford, such that its use has taken on a strange power in our understanding (intellectus) of ourselves and of what it means to know. The pecu- liar allure of IT arises on two counts. On the one hand, IT offers us the false promise of knowing everything, or, at the very least, of gaining access to seemingly infinite infor- mation about the world-as-object; on the other hand, it purports to make available an ersatz transcendence, or a kind of substitute for the joy experienced relationally in a true

(8)

community of being with others, with the world, and with the divine. Put more simply, in terms developed and clarified by Martin Buber, computer technologies promise us a form of omniscience in the realm of I-It experience while at the same time offering us assur- ances about our connectivity to all other users in a communal I-Thou world-wide web of being (Buber, 1970). IT has, in this regard, become a widely accepted substitute for the genuine spiritual exercise of pursuing wisdom, or immortalizing.

With a high degree of prescience at the beginning of the age of personal comput- ers, the Venerable Chan Buddhist Master Hsuan Hua referred to computers—like their predecessors in television and radio—as “people eaters” and “man-eating goblins” inas- much as their use typically causes human beings to “forget about everything else” (Hua, 1985). Ironically, the promise of computers—literally “electric brains” in Chinese—

to increase student engagement and educational accessibility may actually serve most powerfully to undermine our awareness of and attention to what is—the everything else of which Hsuan Hua speaks. Also writing at the beginning of the age of computers, the Canadian philosopher George Grant challenged the notion that computers are simply neutral instruments in our hands:

The phrase “the computer does not impose” misleads, because it abstracts the computer from the destiny that was required for its making. Common sense may tell us that the computer is an instrument, but it is an instrument from within the destiny which does ‘impose’ itself upon us, and therefore the computer does im- pose. (1986, p. 23)

The destiny of which Grant speaks is that dominant form of knowing that treats the world strictly as an object for mastery by the critical-analytic intellect, which un- derstands everything only in terms of its use. Following Grant’s (1986) insights about technology, we might say that our modern educational penchant for IT has been formed from within this destiny wherein “information is about objects, and comes forth as part of that science which summons objects to give us their reasons” (p. 24). Moreover, Grant calls the technological destiny that brought forth the computer “homogenizing” (p. 24);

when the only legitimate way of knowing the world is to treat it as an object, then what is known must always be “thrown over against” (ob-iectum) oneself. In such an homogeniz- ing environment, what is known is not known through a relation of love in which the be- loved is known by the lover—as Romeo knows Juliet, as the philosopher loves wisdom,

(9)

or in theoria, as seer and seen are united. Quite the opposite, in technological society, true knowledge of any object is premised upon the suspension of love in objectivity. As “the ontology of the age” (Grant, 1986, p. 32), technological knowing—the knowing in which the computer finds its origin—is founded upon the denial of love as a legitimate way of knowing (Grant, 1986, p. 35–78; cf. Palmer, 1993, p. 1–16). Using Buber’s distinctions, modern technological knowing is an all-encompassing I-It knowing that dominates to the exclusion of I-Thou knowing (1970). Most important for our study is Grant’s insight that, at the heart of the technological ontology from which has arisen our modern penchant for computers necessarily lies the rejection of both philosophy and contemplation—of what Arthur Zajonc has referred to as “an epistemology of love” (Zajonc, 2006, p. 1742–1759).

There is a true lie (alethos pseudos) at the heart of our fervour and our faith in technology that has resulted in a mass deformation of consciousness; it is a lie about the things that are (ta onta), or what Socrates in the Republic calls a lie about the most sov- ereign things (ta kyriotata) to what is most sovereign (to kyriotato) in ourselves (Plato, 1961, 382ab). Certainly, an infinite number of things may be known as objects, just as an infinite number of things might also be used. The sort of infinite knowing that IT offers us in this regard depends upon our becoming users. The lie and consequent deformation of consciousness in our acceptance of IT’s alluring promise is not that a myriad of things might be known as use-objects by computer users; nor is it that IT can provide us with access to this sort of knowing. The lie is rather that adopting the stance of the user is the only way of knowing the world, that being cut off from the network is akin to being cut off from all knowing, and that all knowledge and enjoyment is necessarily mediated to us through our status as users and, specifically, by our use of computer technologies.

In order to understand the deformation of consciousness that has occurred, it is valuable to examine St. Augustine’s famous distinction between use (uti) and enjoyment (frui). In his work, On Christian Doctrine, Augustine writes:

There are some things, then, which are to be enjoyed, others which are to be used, others still which we enjoy and use. Those things which are objects of enjoyment make us happy. Those things which are objects of use assist, and (so to speak) support us in our efforts after happiness, so that we can attain the things that make us happy and rest in them. We ourselves, again, who enjoy and use these things, being placed among both kinds of objects, if we set ourselves to enjoy those

(10)

which we ought to use, are hindered in our course, and sometimes even led away from it; so that, getting entangled in the love of lower gratifications, we lag behind in, or even altogether turn back from, the pursuit of the real and proper objects of enjoyment. (Augustine, www.ccel.org/ccel/augustine/doctrine.html)

To enjoy a thing means to accept it for and by itself and to find joy in it. To use a thing, by contrast, is to make it the means to obtain what we enjoy. According to Augus- tine, the world of things must be used, but not enjoyed; only God may be enjoyed. Put another way, we ought only to enjoy the things of this world inasmuch as we use them to enjoy God, in which all things participate by virtue of their being—that is, by virtue of their goodness, their beauty, and their truth.

Our fascination with computer technologies has led us to confuse use (uti) with enjoyment (frui). Certainly, human beings are regularly beset by temptations and confu- sions whereby we, as Augustine notes above, set ourselves to enjoy those things which we ought to use. The inappropriate enjoyment of worldly things is not a specifically technological development, however; the particular danger of computer technology lies more in its similarity with sorcery as a magical means of supposing that we might enjoy by use what must not be used through becoming its users. That is, when we relate to the transcendent—i.e., that which may be enjoyed but never used—as computer users who seek out true community through a relation of technological mastery, we are essentially engaged in the same activity as the ancient sorcerer who attempts to compel the gods to work favours for him. This paper suggests that genuine contemplative practices are the best way to extricate both students and teachers from this delusion.

The allure of IT confuses us in two respects about use (uti) and enjoyment (frui).

First, it purports to offer us all knowledge of the things that are (ta onta). Indeed, the Internet is believed to make all the world’s knowledge immediately accessible at the click of a few buttons. It offers users access to seemingly infinite information—certainly more than can be contained in any book—that may be found instantly and that is constantly being updated in real time. This technological promise of infinite knowledge is best illus- trated by the web’s most popular search engine, Google, whose name is a misspelling of the mid-twentieth century term googol. Officially defined as “10 raised to the hundredth power” (New Shorter Oxford English Dictionary, 1993), the term (along with its variant googolplex) was originally coined in 1938 by the nine-year-old nephew of mathematician

(11)

Edward Kasner in order to name the largest countable number this side of infinity, or

“one, followed by writing zeroes until you get tired” (Kasner and Newman, 1940).

Google Corporation self-consciously sells itself as a kind of God-like knowing of all that human beings have ever come to know or understand. This practically infinite knowledge of the world is made available only to users such that knowing by using is held to be the exclusive means towards omniscient—and in this regard, immortalizing—knowledge.

However, by making our participation in divine omniscience conditional upon our status as users, computer technology obscures our awareness of what constitutes genuine im- mortalization—namely, the pursuit of wisdom. We are duped into believing that becom- ing users is the only way to know ta onta; indeed, there is a deeper and more fundamental knowing that is lost to our consciousness when it becomes over-ridden with the fervour of such technological promises. This obscured form of knowing does not entail use, and it arises as a testimony to the truth that not all things derive their enjoyment from use. This realization is experientially available to all of us whenever we adopt the relational I-Thou attitude wherein the one who sees is united by loving gaze with the seen; it is this relation that is cultivated and embodied in genuine contemplation or theoria, and it is precisely this sort of knowing that the googol-knowing or the all-knowing of IT implicitly denies.

Hence, in its offer to provide us with access to all knowing, IT appears to tell the truth, but in fact invites us to suppose we know what we do not know. As students and teach- ers, when we are enticed by the fervour surrounding technological innovation, we easily become ignorant of our own ignorance, and hence are liable to what Gareth Matthews has called “pretentious learning” (Matthews, 1980, p. 94). In this regard, our faith in comput- er technology serves to impede the pursuit of wisdom in schools.

Second, at the same time as it offers us omniscient, world-as-object knowledge, IT simultaneously proposes to deliver an ersatz or substitute mode of theoria. Particularly among young people, constant interface with networked communications provides them with a feeling that they are connected in an I-Thou relation to their friends, to their inti- mates, and, more generally, to the things that are. Moreover, such technologies provide this theoretical substitute as something that is mediated by use (uti)—that is, inasmuch as we become users of technology, we are connected to everyone and everything else.

The geometric complement of this claim, of course, is that inasmuch as we are not users of technology, we are not connected to anyone or anything else. I surmise that it is for this reason that so many of the young people I have taught report a deep spiritual need

(12)

for their technological devices. Indeed, the allure of technology for young people—far more than its claim to offer us infinite knowledge of the world-of-objects, which per- haps entices teachers to a much greater degree—is that it espouses the ability to render the enjoyment (frui) of a transcendent I-Thou relation through the mode of use (uti) that is associated with I-It experience. IT claims for itself magical powers to render known through use (uti) what cannot be known through use, but only through enjoyment (frui).

This delusion, which has begun to be recognized by modern psychologists, results in compulsive Internet use, depression, and loneliness (van den Eijnden, Meekerk, Vermults, Spijkerman, Engels, 2008, 655–665). Josef Pieper’s philosophic writings from 1966 are particularly enlightening when read in light of what has become the mass phenomenon of ersatz transcendence in the googolplex of technology:

Where considerations of pure ‘usefulness’ reign supreme, there will appear, almost inevitably, certain phony replicas, counterfeit imitations of the genuine religious, artistic, and philosophical endeavour. The danger lies in the difficulty of recognizing the deception, or rather, the self-deception; it seems, since all areas are “covered,” there is nothing missing. The place of genuine prayer, for instance, may be taken by some “magical” practice, the attempt to put supernatural powers at our disposal, even to make God himself into a mere functional potency that becomes part of the utilitarian purposes of worldly calculations. (p. 35)

It is important to remember that genuine theoria can never be cultivated through the medium of use. As Pieper points out, “We can only be theoretical in the full sense of the word ... so long as the world is something other (and something more) than a field for human activity, its material, or even its raw material” (1981, p. 116–117). Theoria is rather destroyed by the medium of use, and inasmuch as we are simply users, we are not theoretic in our disposition toward reality. As long as we conceive of ourselves solely as users—and even if we crave transcendence as so many young people do, but are duped into believing that transcendence is a matter of use—we are necessarily incapacitated for the pursuit of wisdom. In this regard, our fascination with ICT outcomes may serve as perhaps one of the greatest impediments to the cultivation of wisdom in schools. As Pieper remarks, “the suicide of philosophy is this—once the world begins to be looked upon merely as the raw material of human activity, it is only a step to the abolition of the theoretical character of philosophy” (1981, p. 117). When offered as a function available

(13)

only to users, the promise of theoretical transcendence serves as a deformation of con- sciousness and marks the destruction of theoria. It distorts our sense of what it means to engage in the contemplative life by deluding us into believing that our I-It experience of computer-use might be a genuine replacement for enjoyment of the I-Thou relation that arises only where use is not present. In diverting us from genuine theorizing—an activity not arising in the atmosphere of use (uti), but in the leisure (schole) of simple enjoyment (frui)—our faith in technology cuts us off from that highest activity of the best part of ourselves in relation to its most perfect object. Aristotle calls this activity “happiness”

(eudaimonia, 2001, Nicomachean Ethics X.vi.2), and this happiness is identical with the- oria as the true mode of our immortalization.

Academics such as R. W. Burniske have suggested that these technological dan- gers can be avoided simply by limiting computer use in schools, by exposing students more consistently to the non-cyberspace world of nature, by using computers to access information about the real world of nature, and by using online discussion boards to discuss the relation between technology and nature (2005, p. 50–52). However, I contend that philosophic, meditative, or contemplative practices among both students and teach- ers are, in fact, the best cure for our technological delusions; such practices involve the recognition of all that is refused by the homogenizing technological ontology. Simply by seeing the truth that is beheld through contemplation, we are released from all the techno- logical delusions that might befall both students and teachers in the modern school. The Ven. Hsuan Hua remarks:

Don’t get scared when you hear me call television, radios, and computers man-eating goblins. No need to be afraid. My hope is that you will clearly rec- ognize these things for what they are. Once you recognize them, then electric gadgets lose their power to confuse you. That’s enough to know. But if you’re confused by them, then they can gobble you down.

The same principle applies to beauty. If the sight of a pretty figure has the power to confuse you, then you’ve been swallowed by a man-eater. If the sight of money confuses you, then you’ve just been devoured by a man-eater. If your purpose is to establish a big reputation, and fame confuses you, then you’ve just been swal- lowed by the goblin of fame. If good food confuses you, although you feel you’ve

(14)

just enjoyed a tasty dish, in fact, the food has eaten you. The food has eaten your spiritual soul, your Dharma-body. It has eaten up your wisdom, and left you as stupid as can be. (1985)

Contemplation and the Danger of Seeing Only What We Have Made

A second problem that arises when we accept the technological ontology is that, if we assume that all of our knowing depends upon our becoming users, we come to accept that we only really know those things that we ourselves have made. As makers and as users of what we have made, our gaze is narrowed and fixed upon the products of our own cre- ative powers; consequently, it is diverted from what we have not made—the everything else of which Hsuan Hua speaks. Our technological gaze therefore lacks the openness of the philosophic gaze that seeks to know reality as such; but the very possibility for theoria rests upon our ability to be receptive to what is apart from our own making and control. What Pieper refers to as the precondition for wisdom’s pursuit—namely, the acknowledgement that reality is “good in itself” (1981, p. 120) even apart from being mastered, made, or transformed by human efforts—is absent where the goodness of what is depends upon its being made by us according to our specifications and personal prefer- ences. James Schall write:

Teachers and students are in the same condition with regard to truth—they stand before something neither the one nor the other made. The modern idea that the only truth is the ‘truth’ we ourselves make is a narrow view that quickly cuts us off from what is. (2001, p. 65)

We should therefore be much more cautious about the pervasive manner in which technology is being incorporated into classroom learning for our young, impressionable students; the narrowing of their gaze that occurs as a result of their continual immersion in the technological paradigm of knowing-as-making affects not only the way that they see the world, but also the way that they see and interact with each other. In particular, some evidence has been found to suggest that rather than opening students to the re- lational knowing-as-loving that is cultivated through contemplative or noetic studies,

(15)

technology instead encourages them to focus on control over inter-personal interactions (Madell, Muncer, 2007, 137–140; cf. Pierce, 2009, 1367–1372).

For instance, the technologies with which students are most familiar and which they employ for their most intimate relations are designed to empower them as users in order that they might exert a high degree of control over their social interactions. Indeed, the allure and marketing success of these technologies lies, at least in part, in their ergo- nomic capabilities—that is, in the ease with which all features of the technology might be personalized or shaped according to individual user preferences. Students become easily acclimatized to the high degree of control that these technologies afford, and it is precisely from within this atmosphere of control that they aspire as users to communicate and to commune with one another in a world-wide web of being. However, a true I-Thou relation is not possible where the need to control and to shape everything according to one’s own preferences—to tailor everything according to one’s own individual, “psy- chomental” identity (Eliade, 1958, p. 14)—remains paramount. Indeed, the personalized atmosphere of technological mediation between users only reinforces what contemplative traditions refer to as “the illusion of self.” By contrast, immersion in a true I-Thou rela- tion necessarily involves not the reinforcement of the psychomental “I”—the “i” that is marketed in the iPhone, the iMac, the iPad, and the iPod—but rather the loosening of our attachments to ourselves and our own preferences. Just as true education (like genuine dialogue) can never be child centred or teacher centred, but must instead be truth centred, so too must we be wary of the arc of educational reforms that express too great a fervour for the individualization of education according to psychomental preferences through technological making and mastery.

James Schall writes that, “We become luminous to ourselves only when we know what is not ourselves” (2006, p. 11). Schall bids us to look beyond ourselves for a mea- sure of ourselves. Rather than remaining in the 2500 year-old stream of education that arises from Protagoras’ sophisticated claim that “Man is the measure of all things,” rather than being dazzled by modern educational reforms that ostensibly transform education, but in fact simply offer novel ways of measuring all things according to our own psycho- mental states, one who genuinely pursues wisdom must seek a true Measure (Metron) of all things. It is for this reason that Plato writes against Protagoras in his Laws that “the god is the measure of all things in the highest degree” (1961, 716c). Protagoras allowed that Man (ho anthropos), as a species, ought to be considered as this measure, and neither

(16)

modern educational reforms nor the IT that supports them can be accurately described as a revolution in Protagorean education. Rather, they are only more of the same, and can perhaps be more aptly characterized as a kind of hyper-actualization of the Protagorean dictum, wherein not the generic Man, but the atomized individual—or for that matter, the individual’s own fluctuating psychomental states—is, and ought to be, the measure of all things. James Conroy expresses similar concerns over finding the correct measure in ed- ucation when he criticizes “growing calls for an individualized, negotiated curriculum,”

wherein “not man but the individual is to be the measure of all things” (2008, p. 148).

Burniske’s solution to the sophistic of modern technological education is to say neither Man nor the individual, but rather Nature is the true Metron. However, following the ancient philosophers and the world’s wisdom traditions, even Nature cannot be its own measure. Contemplative seeing—that unbounded seeing that seeks the true Metron and to know reality as such—is the most powerful and best way of overcoming the dangers of the technological attitude that sees only what it has made.

Contemplation (contemplatio) as Opposed to Lust of the Eyes (concupiscentia oculorum)

Our fascination with IT, like our penchant for gazing upon the television, is problematic for a third reason. As we have seen, Thurman remarks that when we talk about seeking to increase and intensify contemplative mind in our culture, “we are actually talking about methods of transferring contemplative energies from one focus to another” (2006, p. 1766). Students who gaze into the screens of their laptops, their iPhones, their iPads, and other communications devices are certainly engaged in a kind of seeing; however, their surfing on these devices is by and large a distracted and inattentive gaze “in which sensory dissatisfaction is constantly reinforced, anger and violence is imprinted, and confusion and the delusion of materialism is constructed and maintained” (Thurman, 2006, p. 1766). Indeed, the very term surfing implies sliding along the surface of things for the stimulation that it provides, never going down (katabasis) into the depth of things or deriving any insight into the things that are (ta onta). Our proclivity for such techno- logical surfing arises as a result of our not knowing what to do with ourselves in our free time—that is, with this precious time of life in which students are not compelled to work

(17)

for a living and teachers are granted the most wonderful of all gifts in having an occupa- tion that provides them with the opportunity to share their eagerness to pursue wisdom with their students and to beckon them towards the study and search for what is.

Students in school do not generally know what it really means to be in school.

I frequently break into a smile when I pick up my youngest child from Grade 2. At the sound of the bell that marks the end of the day, a troupe of young boys very often bursts through the school doors (barely stopping to open them!) with a cheer and a roar of de- light as though they were being released from prison. Schools—our only non-religious in- stitutionalized places of leisure or schole—do not cultivate the experience of leisure (Lt.

otium), with the result that the possibilty for otium is replaced by experiences of enmity or aversion (Lt. odium). Indeed, both teachers and students are so unfamiliar with what it means to engage in leisure or schole that the liberty of the socially prescibed free space in which true schooling might take place becomes a problem for us—a problem we most often address with busy work, with evermore-diverse modes of technological stimulation, and with numerous distractions that masquerade as engaged learning. However, what is needed in this situation is not more stimulation to engage learners, but rather less stim- ulation in order to develop more careful attention so that awareness of the significance of schole might be generated, and so that we might begin to cultivate the experience and practice of schole in the classroom. What is needed is something akin to the silence dis- cussed in the introduction to this paper that enables us to listen, to be open and receptive.

Marilyn Nelson has commented on how the noise of technology might actually serve to impede this sort of listening:

How can we teach young Americans to listen to silence? The noise of our lives is—sometimes literally—deafening. Technology has given us the 24-hour soundtrack, our own background music, our “score.” . . . When do young Ameri- cans ever experience silence? Perhaps only when they are glaring reproachfully at their parents with their arms folded. (2006, p. 1734)

As many academics have noted, in our current school environment, “the demands for constant activity, the habit of electronic stimulation, and the production orientation of modern society make it very difficult to keep the contemplative alive” (Hart, 2004, p. 43).

In such an “era of fragmentation, ever-increasing speed, multi-tasking, and continuously interrupted attention” (Haynes, 2005, p. 8), what is needed, as Thurman suggests, is the

(18)

re-direction of our natural desire to see. Essentially, what is needed is the introduction of some form of contemplative practice into the classroom.

In my experience of student inquiry in the classroom, much of what passes for learning is best described by the Latin term curiositas as opposed to studiositas. The contrasting psychological meanings of these words are respectively “intemperate in- quisitiveness” (curiositas) and the “temperate desire for knowledge” (studiositas). Both studiositas and curiositas arise from the natural wish to see. However, studiositas dis- tinguishes itself as zealous attention in the desire to know what is; it remains true to its objective of seeing what is, and, for this reason, our word “study” has sometimes been called “a prayer to truth” (Sertillanges, 1998, p. 69). By contrast, curiositas is associated with meddlesomeness—the polypragmosyne or “doing-of-many-things” that the Greeks took as their definition of injustice. It is a kind of many-knowing that seeks out the expe- rience and the stimulation of seeing rather than what is seen. Curiositas runs amok in the contemporary technological classroom where one-to-one policies make it every child’s right to have a networked computer at all times. Instead of being studious, students engage in all sorts of distractions and multi-tasking, such as playing computer games, social networking, watching mindless spectacles on Youtube, or even shopping online.

Essentially, curiositas arises wherever the desire to see is not rooted in the desire to take up whatever is seen toward the most beautiful (kallistos) of sights. The allure of technolo- gy for many young people is not that it engages them in learning about what is, but rather that it provides them with a means of escape from themselves and from the hollowness of being rootless in school, which, prior to computer technologies, found its release along other routes. Indeed, Pieper’s comments on the nature of curiositas serve as particularly apt descriptions of many classrooms:

The degeneration into curiositas of the natural wish to see may be much more than a harmless confusion on the surface of the human being. It may be the sign of complete rootlessness. It may mean that man has lost his capacity for living with himself; that, in flight from himself, nauseated and bored by the void of an interior life gutted by despair, he is seeking with selfish anxiety and on a thousand futile paths that which is given only to the noble stillness of a heart held ready for sacri- fice and thus in possession of itself, namely the fullness of being. (1981, p. 86)

(19)

Citing the Journals of André Gide, Pieper (1981) remarks that lacking cultivat- ed exposure to the experience and practice of leisure, we tend to encounter time that is not filled with work as “deadly emptiness” and “endless ennui” (p. 122). School—but also life outside of school—becomes for us a kind of spiritual desert as a result of “the destruction of the vita contemplativa” (p. 122). We become prone in our freedom (now experienced as spiritual displeasure and discomfort) to seek escape—or perhaps I might co-opt the term “e-scape” from gerontological and management studies (Buse, 2010, p.

987–1009; Moshinskie, 2001, p. 30–37) as it relates specifically to the use of computer technologies among students and educators—in the distracted movements of the interest- ed eye that careens from one object to the next in search of novelty and titillation. This desire to see resembles contemplation (contemplatio) inasmuch as it is a kind of gaze.

However, whereas the contemplative gaze seeks to know reality, the gaze of the unlei- sured eye is, by contrast, concerned with the pleasure to be derived from seeing rather than the seeing of what is for its own sake.

This unleisured seeing is, effectively, what is meant in Christian philosophy by the phrase “lust of the eyes” (concupiscentia oculorum). Pieper writes,

There is a gratification in seeing that reverses the original meaning of vision [i.e., contemplation] and works disorder in man himself. The true meaning of seeing is perception of reality. But “concupiscience of the eyes” does not aim to perceive reality, but to enjoy “seeing.” (1981, p. 86)

Augustine has written an extensive psychology of concupiscentia oculorum in his Con- fessions. He contends that all sins are derived either singularly or from any combination of “lust of the flesh” or “carnal desire” (concupiscentia carnis), the “lust of the eyes”

(concupiscentia oculorum), and the “empty pomp of living” or the “pride of life” (ambi- tione saeculi, 1961, 10.30.41; cf. 3.8.6). Numbered among these three root categories of sin, concupiscentia oculorum is a “vain” or “unhealthy curiosity” (curiosa cupiditas) that seeks not what is truly desirable, but rather the satisfaction of its own inquisitiveness (1961, 10.35.54–55). Augustine sees this sort of inquisitiveness at the heart of scientific investigations when they are divested of any concern for the Highest Good (Summum Bonum), and he likens such pursuits to a kind of sorcery or magic (artes magicas) that seeks to obtain knowledge for perverted purposes: “not in the hope of salvation, but sim- ply for the love of the experience” (1961, 10.35.55).

(20)

Augustine’s psychological analysis locates the root cause of concupiscentia ocu- lorum in the inordinate love of worldly things: in misjudging the nature of things through not seeking out the true Metron of all these goods in the Supreme Good, or Summum Bo- num. His psychology is therefore deeply rooted in the tradition of Christian contemplative practice, which involves not the heightening of our sense of self-importance, self-regard, or self-love (amor sui), but rather, as Socrates describes in Plato’s Republic, a turning of the soul (periagoge, 1961, 518d ff) away from all these finite goods towards the one true good to be found in the love of wisdom. In Augustine’s estimation, this love of wisdom is identical with the love of God (amor Dei, 1972, VIII.1, 298). As the author of John’s first epistle recommends:

Do not love the world or the things in the world. The love of the Father is not in those who love the world; for all that is in the world—the desire of the flesh, the desire of the eyes, the pride in riches—comes not from the Father but from the world. And the world and its desire are passing away, but those who do the will of God live forever. (1 John 2:15–17)

For Augustine—as for all who pursue wisdom—a genuine education must be immortalizing. Aristotle writes that the immortalization (to athanatizein) brought about through contemplative practice is the precise activity of our highest happiness (eu- daimonia). According to Anaxagoras, contemplative practice (theoria) is what we were born for (Aristotle, 2001, Eudemian Ethics i.5 1216a11). In Plato’s Symposium, Dioti- ma remarks that “it is in contemplating (theomenoi) the Beautiful Itself (auto to kalon)”

that “human life is to be lived,” (Plato, 1961, 211d) for it is only “when a human being looks (blepontos) there and contemplates (theomenou) that with that by which one must contemplate it, and be with it” that true virtue is begotten in him, making him “dear to god” (theophilei), and “if any other among men is immortal (athanato), he is too”

(Plato, 1961, 212a).

(21)

Conclusion

Contemplation or theoria ought to take greater precedence in education than is currently the case. More specifically, we must encourage a noetic taking up (anairesis) of whatever is seen towards its ground in what is the highest or best (Ariston) of sights. Our modern focus on and fascination with IT serves in many ways to thwart and to discourage the cultivation of noetic studies and the pursuit of wisdom in schools. If the significance of intellectus and the cognitive movements of noesis could be made clear and convincing to educational policy makers, it seems likely that the appropriateness of leisure or schole might be recognized and its practice rendered more frequent.

References

Aristotle. (2001). The basic works. Richard McKeon (Ed.). New York: Modern Library.

Augustine. (1972). City of God. (John O’Meara, Trans.). London: Penguin. Latin text available online at www.thelatinlibrary.com/august.html

Augustine. On Christian doctrine. Grand Rapids, MI: Christian Classics Ethereal Library.

www.ccel.org/ccel/augustine/doctrine.html

Buber, Martin. (1970). I and thou. (Walter Kaufmann, Trans.). New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

Burniske, R. W. (2005). Sharing the sacred fire: Integrating educational technology without annihilating nature. TechTrends, 49(6), 50–52.

Buse, Christina E. (2010). E-scaping the ageing body? Computer technologies and embodiment in later life. Ageing and Society, 30, 987–1009.

Conroy, James C. (2008). Philosophy, wisdom, and reading great books. In Michael Hand and Carrie Winstanley (Eds.), Philosophy in Schools (pp. 145–157). London:

Continuum.

Eliade, Mircea. (1958). Yoga: Immortality and freedom. (Willard R. Trask, Trans.).

Bollingen Series 56. New York: Princeton University Press.

Freeman, Laurence. (July 2012). A letter from Laurence Freeman. Meditatio Newsletter:

International Edition, 36(2), 1–5.

(22)

Garrison Institute. (2005). Contemplation and education—Current status of programs using contemplative techniques in K–12 educational settings: A mapping report.

Garrison, New York.

Garrison Institute. (2009). Garrison institute report: Envisioning the future of contemplative education. October 22–24, 2008. Garrison, New York.

Grant, George Parkin. (1986). Technology and justice. Toronto: Anansi.

Hart, Tobin. (2004). Opening the contemplative mind in the classroom. Journal of Transformative Education, 2(1), 28–46.

Haynes, Deborah. (2005). Contemplative practice and the education of the whole person.

ARTS: The Arts in Religious and Theological Studies, 16(2), 8–10.

Hua, Venerable Master Hsuan. (1985). “Electric Brains’ and other menaces. Transcript of a Dharma Talk (Vancouver, 1985). Retrieved from http://online.sfsu.edu/rone/

Buddhism/VenHua/electricbrains.html (accessed Jan. 23, 2014)

Kasner, Edward & Newman, James. (1940). Mathematics and the imagination. Redmond, WA: Tempus Books of Microsoft Press.

Madell, Dominic E., & Muncer, Steven J. (2007). Control over social interactions: An important reason for young people’s use of the internet and mobile phones for communication? CyberPsychology and Behaviour, 10(1), 137–140.

Matthews, Gareth B. (1980). Philosophy and the young child. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Moshinskie, Jim. (2001). How to keep e-learners from e-scaping. Performance Improvement, 30–37.

Nelson, Marilyn. (2006). The fruit of silence. Teachers College Record, 108(9), 1733–1741.

The New Oxford Annotated Bible. (1991). Bruce M. Metzger and Roland E. Murphy (Eds.). New Revised Standard Version. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Palmer, Parker J. (1993). To know as we are known: Education as a spiritual journey. San Francisco, CA: Harper One.

Pieper, Josef. (1966). In defence of philosophy: Classical wisdom stands up to modern challenges. (Lothar Krauth, Trans.). San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press.

(23)

Pieper, Josef. (1981). Josef Pieper: An anthology. San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press.

Pierce, Tamyra. (2009). Social anxiety and technology: Face-to-face communication versus technological communication among teens. Computers in Human Behavior, 25, 1367–1372.

Plato. (1961). The collected dialogues. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (Eds.).

Bollingen Series 71. Princeton, CT: Princeton University Press.

Posnett, Charles, & Posnett, Patricia. (2013). Meditation and education: The gift of simplicity. London, UK: Meditatio.

Schall, James V. (2001). On the unseriousness of human affairs: Teaching, writing, playing, believing, lecturing, philosophizing, singing, dancing. Wilmington, DE:

ISI Books.

Sertillanges, A. G. (1998). The intellectual life. (Mary Ryan, Trans.). Washington, DC:

Catholic University of America Press.

Thurman, Robert. (2006). Meditation and education: Buddhist India, Tibet, and modern America. Teachers College Record, 108(9), 1765–1774. (Also available at www.contemplativemind.org)

van den Eijnden, R. J., Meerkerk, G. J., Vermulst, A.A., Spijkerman, R., & Engels, R. C.

(2008). Online communication, compulsive internet use, and psychosocial well- being among adolescents: A longitudinal study. Developmental Psychology, 44(3), 655–665.

Références

Documents relatifs

Compte tenu de notre revue do- cumentaire, deux solutions s’offrent à nous, soit le trans- fert de la préparation à la banque de sang qui dispose d’une hotte de classe

For the solar atmosphere, the application of the connectivity-based helicity flux density method relies on approximate 3D solutions obtained from force-free field (FFF)

To sum up, Chalmers’s proposal of an early mandatory support by a qualified majority of national parliaments would result in greater domination by governments in the legislative

The policy proposals in the second group suggest that the French government should dedicate human and financial resources toward food waste prevention and recycling goals and

-Details on quantitative analyses (e.g., data treatment and statistical scripts in R, bioinformatic pipeline scripts, etc.) and details concerning simulations (scripts,

(1) a small committee of three experts, with "broad knowledge of insecticides and their uses, including representatives of the more important existing 'national

Since a few years, these NGOs have been working in close cooperation with several Yemeni organisations for the defence of freedom of the press and expression (The Yemen Female Media

These models allow managers to determine the best time for replacement investment of equipment under technological evolution but do not consider the maintenance strategies as well