• Aucun résultat trouvé

Digression: The Small Object Argument

LetC be a category containing a collection of morphisms{fα:Cα →Dα}, and letg :X →Z be another morphism in C. Under some mild hypotheses, Quillen’s small object argument can be used to produce a factorization

X g

0

→Y g

00

→Z

whereg0is “built from” the morphismsfα, andg00has the right lifting property with respect to the morphisms fα(see§T.A.1.2 for a detailed discussion). The small object argument was originally used by Grothendieck to prove that every Grothendieck abelian category has enough injective objects (see [25] or Corollary A.1.3.4.7).

It is now a basic tool in the theory of model categories.

Our goal in this section is to carry out an∞-categorical version of the small object argument (Proposition 1.4.7). We begin by introducing some terminology.

Definition 1.4.1. LetCbe an∞-category. Letf :C→D andg:X →Y be morphisms inC. We will say thatg has theright lifting propertywith respect tof if every commutative diagram

C //

f

X

g

D //Y can be extended to a 3-simplex ofC, as depicted by the diagram

C //

f

X

g

D

>>//Y.

In this case, we will also say thatf has theleft lifting propertywith respect tog.

More generally, if S is any set of morphisms inC, we will say that a morphism g has the right lifting propertywith respect toS if it has the right lifting property with respect to every morphism inS, and that a morphismf has theleft lifting propertywith respect toS iff has the left lifting property with respect to every morphism inS.

Definition 1.4.2. LetCbe an∞-category and let S be a collection of morphisms inC. We will say that a morphism f in C is a transfinite pushout of morphisms in S if there exists an ordinal αand a diagram F : N[α]→C(here [α] denotes the linearly ordered set of ordinals{β :β ≤α}) with the following properties:

(1) For every nonzero limit ordinalλ≤α, the restrictionF|N[λ] is a colimit diagram inC. (2) For every ordinalβ < α, the morphismF(β)→F(β+ 1) is a pushout of a morphism inS.

(3) The morphismF(0)→F(α) coincides withf.

Remark 1.4.3. LetC be an∞-category, and let S andT be collections of morphisms inC. Suppose that every morphism belonging toT is a transfinite pushout of morphisms inS. Iff is a transfinite pushout of morphisms inT, thenf is a transfinite pushout of morphisms inS.

Definition 1.4.4. LetCbe an∞-category and letS be a collection of morphisms inC. We will say thatS isweakly saturatedif it has the following properties:

(1) Iff is a morphism inCwhich is a transfinite pushout of morphisms inS, then f ∈S.

(2) The setS is closed under retracts. In other words, if we are given a commutative diagram C

f //C0

f0

//C

f

D //D0 //D

in which both horizontal compositions are the identity andf0 belongs toS, then so does f.

Remark 1.4.5. If C is the nerve of an ordinary category (which admits small colimits), then Definition 1.4.4 reduces to Definition T.A.1.2.2.

Remark 1.4.6. Let S be a weakly saturated collection of morphisms in an∞-category C. Any identity map inC can be written as a transfinite composition of morphisms in S (take α= 0 in Definition 1.4.2).

Condition (2) of Definition 1.4.4 guarantees that the class of morphisms is stable under equivalence; it follows that every equivalence inCbelongs toS. Condition (1) of Definition 1.4.4 also implies thatSis closed under composition (takeα= 2 in Definition 1.4.2).

We can now formulate our main result, which we will prove at the end of this section.

Proposition 1.4.7 (Small Object Argument). Let C be a presentable ∞-category and let S be a small collection of morphisms in C. Then every morphismf :X→Z admits a factorizaton

X f

0

→Y f

00

→Z

wheref0 is a transfinite pushout of morphisms inS andf00 has the right lifting property with respect toS.

Warning 1.4.8. In contrast with the ordinary categorical setting (see Proposition T.A.1.2.5), the factor-ization

of Proposition 1.4.7 cannot generally be chosen to depend functorially onf.

To apply Proposition 1.4.7, the following observation is often useful:

Proposition 1.4.9. Let C be an ∞-category and let T be a collection of morphisms in C. Let S denote the collection of all morphisms in Cwhich have the left lifting property with respect toT. Then S is weakly saturated.

Proof. Since the intersection of a collection of weakly saturated collections is weakly saturated, it will suffice to treat the case where T consists of a single morphism g : X → Y. Note that a morphism f : C → D has the left lifting property with respect tog if and only if, for every lifting of Y to Cf /, the induced map θf : Cf / /Y → CC/ /Y is surjective on objects which lie over g ∈ C/Y. Sinceθf is a left fibration, it is a categorical fibration; it therefore suffices to show that object of CC/ /Y which lies overg is in the essential image ofθf. We begin by showing thatSis stable under pushouts. Suppose we are given a pushout diagram σ: of g to Cλ/ /Y lies in the essential image of θ, which follows from our assumption that every lifting of g to CC0/ /Y lies in the essential image ofθf0.

We now verify condition (1) of Definition 1.4.4. Fix an ordinary αand a diagramF : [α]→Csatisfying the hypotheses of Definition 1.4.2, and letf :F(0)→F(α) be the induced map. Choose a lifting ofY toCf / remains to treat the case of a successor ordinal: letβ < αand assume thatXβ has been defined; we wish to show that the vertexXβ lies in the image of the mapθβ:CFβ+1/ /Y →CFβ/ /Y. Letu:F(β)→F(β+ 1) be the morphism determined byF, so thatθβ is equivalent to the mapθu. Since the image ofXβ inCF(β)/ /Y

lies overg, the existence of the desired lifting follows from our assumption thatu∈S.

We now verify (2). Consider a diagram σ: ∆2×∆1→C, given by

Assume thatf0 ∈S; we wish to provef ∈S. Choose a lifting ofY toCf /, and liftY further toCσ/ (here we identifyf withσ|({2} ×∆1). LetX be a lifting ofg toCC/ /Y; we wish to show thatX lies in the image of θf. We can lift X further to an objectXe ∈Cσ0/ /Y, where σ0 =σ|(∆2× {0}). Letσ0 =σ|(∆1×∆1).

The forgetful functor θ:Cσ0/ /Y →Cλ/ /Y is equivalent toθf0, so that the image ofXe in Cλ/ /Y lies in the image ofθ. It follows immediately thatX lies in the image ofθf.

Corollary 1.4.10. Let Cbe a presentable ∞-category, let S be a small collection of morphisms of C, letT be the collection of all morphisms in Cwhich have the right lifting property with respect to every morphism in S, and letS be the collection of all morphisms in C which have the left lifting property with respect to every morphism in T. Then S is the smallest weakly saturated collection of morphisms which containsS.

Proof. Proposition 1.4.9 implies thatSis weakly saturated, and it is obvious thatScontainsS. Suppose that S is any weakly saturated collection of morphisms which containsS; we will show that S ⊆S. Let f :X →Z be a morphism in S, and choose a factorization

which shows thatf is a retract off0 and therefore belongs toS as desired.

Recall that ifCis an∞-category which admits finite limits and colimits, then every simplicial objectX of C determines latching and matching objects Ln(X), Mn(X) for n ≥0 (see Remark T.A.2.9.16). The following result will play an important role in our proof of Theorem 1.3.12:

Corollary 1.4.11. Let C be a presentable ∞-category and let S be a small collection of morphisms in C. Let Y be any object of C, and letφ:C/Y →C be the forgetful functor. Then there exists a simplicial object X ofC/Y with the following properties:

(1) For each n≥0, let un :Ln(X)→Xn be the canonical map. Then φ(un) is a transfinite pushout of morphisms inS.

(2) For each n≥0, letvn :Xn →Mn(X)be the canonical map inC/Y. Thenφ(vn) has the right lifting property with respect to every morphism inS.

Proof. We construct X as the union of a compatible family of diagramsX(n) : N(∆≤n)op →C/Y, which we construct by induction onn. The casen=−1 is trivial (since∆≤−1 is empty). Assume thatn≥0 and that X(n−1) has been constructed, so that the matching and latching objects Ln(X), Mn(X) are defined and we have a mapt:Ln(X)→Mn(X). Using Proposition T.A.2.9.14, we see that it suffices to construct

in C/Y. Since the map C/Y → C is a right fibration, this is equivalent to the problem of producing a commutative diagram

in the∞-categoryC. Proposition 1.4.7 guarantees that we are able to make these choices in such a way that (1) and (2) are satisfied.

Remark 1.4.12. In the situation of Corollary 1.4.11, let ∅ denote the initial object of C. Then for each n≥0, the canonical map w:∅ →φ(Xn) is a transfinite pushout of morphisms in S. To prove this, we let P denote the full subcategory of∆[n]/ spanned by the surjective maps [n] → [m]; we will regard P as a partially ordered set. For each upward-closed subset P0 ⊆P, we letZ(P0) denote a colimit of the induced diagram

N(P0)op−→N(∆)op X−→ C/Y

−→φ C.

ThenZ(∅)' ∅ andZ(P)'φ(Xn). It will therefore suffice to show that if P1 ⊆P is obtained from P0 by adjoining a new element given by α: [n]→[m], then the induced map θ: Z(P0)→Z(P1) is a transfinite pushout of morphisms inS. This follows from assertion (1) of Corollary 1.4.11, sinceθ is a pushout of the mapφ(un) :φ(Lm(X))→φ(Xm).

Proof of Proposition 1.4.7. Let S ={gi :Ci →Di}i∈I. Choose a regular cardinal κsuch that each of the objects Ci is κ-compact. We construct a diagram F : N[κ] → C/Z as the union of maps {Fα : N[α] → C/Z}α≤κ; here [α] denotes the linearly ordered set of ordinals{β : β ≤α}. The construction proceeds by induction: we let F0 be the morphism f : X → Z, and for a nonzero limit ordinal λ ≤ κwe let Fλ be a colimit of the diagram obtained by amalgamating themaps {Fα}α<λ. Assume that α < κ and that Fα

been constructed. ThenFα(α) corresponds to a mapX0→Z. LetT(α) be a set of representantives for all equivalence classes of diagrams equivalence classes of diagramsσt:

Ct //

gt

X0

Dt //Z,

wheregt is a morphism belonging toS. Choose a pushout diagram

`

inC/Z. We regardX00as an object ofCX0/ /Z. Since the map (C/Z)Fα/→CX0/ /Z is a trivial Kan fibration, we can liftX0 to an object of (C/Z)Fα/, which determines the desired mapFα+1.

For eachα≤κ, letfα:Yα→Z be the image F(α)∈C/Z. LetY =Yκ andf00=fκ. We claim thatf00 has the right lifting property with respect to every morphism inS. In other words, we wish to show that for eachi∈I and every mapDi→Z, the induced map

MapC

/Z(Di, Y)→MapC

/Z(Ci, Y)

is surjective on connected components. Choose a pointη∈MapC/Z(Ci, Y). SinceCiisκ-compact, the space MapC

/Z(Ci, Y) can be realized as the filtered colimit of mapping spaces lim

−→αMapC showing thatf0 is a transfinite pushout of morphisms inS. Using Remark 1.4.3, we are reduced to showing that for eachα < κ, the mapYα→Yα+1 is a transfinite pushout of morphisms inS. To prove this, choose a well-ordering of T(α) having order type β. For γ < β, let tγ denote the corresponding element ofT(α).

We define a functorG: N[β]→Cso that, for each β0≤β, we have a pushout diagram

It is easy to see that Gsatisfies the conditions of Definition 1.4.2 and therefore exhibits Yα → Yα+1 as a transfinite pushout of morphisms inS.