• Aucun résultat trouvé

+DIEC =@ 5D=HEC

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Partager "+DIEC =@ 5D=HEC"

Copied!
17
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

Choosing and Sharing

Jérémy Laurent-Lucchetti and Justin Leroux †‡

December 15, 2008

Abstract

Implementing a project which benets all involved agents but brings major costs or additional benets to only one is often problematic. Siting a nation- wide nuclear waste disposal or hosting a major sporting event are examples of such a problem: costs or additional benets are tied to the identity of the host.

Our goal is twofold: to choose the ecient site (the host with the lowest cost or highest localized surplus) and to share the exact cost, or surplus, with total control over realized transfers. We propose a simple mechanism to implement both objectives, in the vein of the well-known Divide and Choose procedure.

The unique subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium outcome of our mechanism co- incides with truthtelling, is budget-balanced, individually rational and immune to coalitional deviations. More generally, our mechanism can also be used to handle more complex situations where the usefulness of the projectregardless of its locationis not unanimous.

HEC Montréal, Institut d'Économie Appliquée.

HEC Montréal, Institut d'Économie Appliquée and CIRPÉE.

We are grateful for stimulating conversations with Francis Bloch, Lars Ehlers, Bettina Klaus,

Hervé Moulin, Nicolas Sahuguet, François Salanié and Bernard Sinclair-Desgagné as well as for

feedback from participants of the Canadian Economics Theory Conference, the Canadian Economics

Association Conference, the Montreal Natural Resources and Environmental Economics Workshops

(2)

Keywords: Public goods; local externalities; NIMBY; implementation; mech-

anism design; VCG mechanisms.

(3)

1 Introduction

The search for hazardous waste landlls and nuclear waste repositories in the United States and in many other countries has proven to be a dicult task. Even when oered monetary compensation, very few communities have accepted to host such facilities.

Since the mid-70s only one small radioactive waste disposal facility and a single hazardous waste landll (ttingly located in Last Chance, Colorado) have been sited in the United States (see Gerrard, 1994). Consequently, the U.S. nuclear industry still faces a major problem. Several other similar programs face social rejection from local populations: noxious facilities, prisons, airports, etc. These public goods are socially necessary but come with local externalities (noise, pollution, noxious odors, etc.) or bear a negative connotation. Dierent factors can generate such rejection: the loss in the economic value of property, the loss in the perceived quality of life or the fear of health hazards, etc. In economic terms, these public goods have a private-bad aspect to them which creates a siting problem (the so-called "NIMBY" problem, for

"Not In My Backyard"): all communities benet from the project but only onethe hostwill bear the cost.

Similarly, choosing a host for a project which generates desirable local externali- ties, such as a major international research project (like the International Thermonu- clear Experimental Reactor, ITER) or a major sporting event (the Olympic Games), is no easier task to accomplish. Here, benets accrue to all (as in the "local bad" case) but the host obtains an additional localized surplus. Consequently, all communities compete to be the host. The selection process is then a long and tedious one where each participant tries to prove that it is the best candidate.

For the sake of exposition, we consider the case of a project generating negative

externalities throughout the body of the paper. The overall cost of the project being

tied to the identity of the host, eciency asks that the host be the community with

the lowest hosting cost. In practice, a diculty one faces when implementing such

a project is that the planner typically has access to much less information than the

(4)

involved parties, which causes a revelation problem. Next, another aspect of the siting problem relates to the sharing of the cost borne by the host community so as to guarantee the stability of the agreement. Indeed, the planner may wish to select a specic sharing outcome, which may take into account the voluntary participation of involved communities (no community should pay more than the benets it derives from the project), their budget constraints, the relative size of their population, their respective involvement in the project or any other relevant characteristic. Taking into account such redistribution issues helps ease the siting process itself and reinforces the stability of the agreement. Otherwise, even when the ecient host is identied, there still could exist strong opposition (from the host or other participants) preventing the ecient outcome from occurring. As pointed out in Easterling (1992) and Frey et al. (1996), the structure of the compensation itself could result in the rejection of the project.

We propose a simple mechanism in the vein of the well-known Divide and Choose method which achieves ecient and equitable outcomes. First, communities jointly propose a monetary compensation for the host, which any community can accept thus becoming the hostor reject. If no community accepts the compensation, the most fervent proponent of the project is selected to be the host instead. This mech- anism allows the social planner to achieve the two above-mentioned goals: a redis- tributive goal (the planner can choose the cost-sharing method) and the resolution of the revelation problem.

A well-known class of outcome-ecient mechanisms is that of Vickrey-Clark-

Groves (VCG) mechanisms. Announcing one's true cost is a dominant strategy (thus,

the ecient outcome is chosen) but these mechanisms fail to balance the budget and

generate a surplus which cannot be redistributed between the agents while preserving

the strategic properties of the method (see Moulin, 2007, Section 4, for a VCG treat-

ment of the NIMBY problem). In fact, it is a well-known fact that an ecient and

(5)

budget-balanced outcome cannot be implemented in dominant strategy 1 for direct revelation mechanismsi.e., where agents need only know their own characteristics to behave optimally. Hence, one must impose some informational structure.

One way out of the eciency/incentive compatibility trade-o is to allow the so- cial planner to use statistical information about agents' valuations and to replace dominant strategy equilibrium by Bayesian incentive compatibility. D'Aspremont and Gerard-Varet, 1979, elaborate a mechanism which is Bayesian incentive compat- ible, ecient, and budget-balanced. However, individual rationality is not satised.

Mailath and Postlewaite, 1990, show that if individual rationality is required along with Bayesian incentive compatibility, then it is generally impossible to achieve ef- ciency. Moreover, they show that as the number of involved agents grows, the probability of ever undertaking the ecient project goes to zero.

For the problem at hand, O'Sullivan (1993) investigates Bayesian-Nash equilib- rium behavior under a sealed-bid auction where the community submitting the lowest bid hosts the project and receives the highest bid as compensation (thus failing to bal- ance the budget). In the same vein, Minehart and Neeman (2002) propose a method adapted from a second-price auction to site a project. The project is sited in the community with the lowest cost or, if not (compensation induces misrepresentation of costs), the authors argue that the eciency loss is small when the number of agents is large. The procedure is self-nanced but the host obtains a surplus because it is compensated with the second lowest bid, as in a second-price auction.

Given the likely nature of the applicationthe siting of a single large and durable facility between a handful of neighboring communitieswe opted for a dierent in- formational context where agents have specic information on others' characteristics.

The restrictiveness of our analysis, and of the non-Bayesian implementation literature in general, is in terms of information held (or acquired) by agents: agents must have some information about the preference prole. This is the price to pay for dealing with

1

See Green and Laont, 1979.

(6)

"universal" mechanisms which use no statistical information about the distribution of agents' characteristics. Part of the literature on non-cooperative implementation under complete information has produced general characterization theorems (see Pe- leg, 1978, Maskin, 1999, or Jackson, 2001, for a survey). The resulting mechanisms are very abstract and so general that they often cannot take into account specic restrictions on preferences or specic environments and, thus, are of little help for the siting problem at hand in practice.

Another strand of the literature on non-Bayesian implementation takes advantage of the structure of specic environments in order to produce simpler mechanisms.

For the problem at hand, Perez-Castrillo and Wettstein (2002) require that agents be fully informed about the preference prole and design a mechanism which leads to ecient siting with budget-balanced transfers. However, their mechanism does not allow for any control over transfer payments 2 . We relax their information structure by requiring that each community knows only the lowest hosting cost in the cost prole (and the planner does not). We show that the unique subgame-perfect Nash equi- librium outcome of our mechanism coincides with truth-telling (the host's true cost is revealed). Moreover, the host chosen in equilibrium is an ecient one (whenever carrying out the project turns out to be ecient), the outcome is budget-balanced, individually rational and the planner has total control over realized transfers.

Regarding this issue of accurately allocating costs in a non-Bayesian context, Jack- son and Moulin (1992) jointly handle a revelation problem and redistribution concerns for the traditional case of a pure public good. As such, their mechanism considers only one possible project and therefore cannot address the issue of selection which is central in this paper. Moreover, while the non-Bayesian informational context is crucial for our results to hold, it should be pointed out that, even in perfect informa- tion, second price auctions à la Minehart & Neeman (2002) would admit a continuum

2

Ehlers (2007) considers a "natural" variant of Perez-Castrillo and Wettstein's mechanism. He

shows that this interpretation puts severe restrictions on the existence of Nash equilibria. In partic-

ular, no equilibrium exists when only one project is ecient.

(7)

of equilibria between the lowest and the second lowest hosting cost, thus rendering inaccurate the redistribution of costs.

The mechanism we propose proceeds in two stages. In the rst stage, each com- munity announces the lowest cost if the project were to be sited in a community other than itself (the community announcing the lowest such cost will be referred to as the "optimist"). In the second stage, each community other than the "optimist"

announces its own cost of hosting the project. The host is then selected among those communities which announce the lowest cost in the second stage, provided it accepts the compensation announced by the optimist. If not, the optimist becomes the host.

This Divide and Choose structure guarantees truthful revelation from the optimist.

In addition to being able to handle the other symmetric situation where benets accrue to all and the host obtains an additional benet (e.g., Olympic Games), our mechanism can be used to handle a much larger class of situations. For instance, certain categories of people may obtain negative benets if a given project is carried out, independently of where it is sited (e.g., some communities may frown upon the use of nuclear energy in general). In that case, our mechanism can allow for these communities to be compensated in addition to the host should building the project be ecient. In our framework, the preferences of the communities are driven by two parameters: a component which represents the preferences of each community with regard to the existence of the project independently of its location, and a local component which is tied to the local positive or negative externalities if hosting the project.

2 The Model

Let N = {1, ..., n} be the set of communities, with n 2 . Each community i = 1, ....n

obtains a benet, b i R , if the project is carried outregardless of its location

(8)

and incurs a cost, c i R , if it is chosen to host the project 3 . We take the view that c i encompasses the actual construction cost of the project plus the disutility of community i from hosting the project, both of which are localized and community- specic. Let b = (b i ) i²N be the prole of benets and c = (c i ) i²N be the cost prole.

Without loss of generality we rank communities from lowest to highest hosting cost:

c 1 c 2 .... c n . The prole of benets is known to the planner 4 . The cost prole is unknown to the planner but it is common knowledge that each community i knows c 1 and its own c i . The total payo of community i if the project is carried out is given by:

u i = b i I(i = host)c i t i (1)

where t i are transfers paid by community i and I(i = host) is the indicator function equal to 1 if i is the host and 0 otherwise. Eciency requires the good to be built if P

N b i c 1 and hosted by a community h such that c h = c 1 . If P

N b i < c 1 , the project should not be built.

We design a mechanism which selects a host community and assigns cost-shares α i (θ)c h to each community i , where θ represents a number of exogenous (and known) characteristics relevant for sharing the cost 5 and where P

N α i (θ) = 1 . We view it as the planner's responsibility to ensure that the sharing method induces individual rationality (i.e., b i α i (θ)c 1 0 for all i ) 6 .

3

For clarity, we use a benet and cost interpretation, but note that each parameter can be positive or negative.

4

Note that, if the prole of benets is not immediately accessible to the planner, one could easily embed the mechanisms proposed in Jackson and Moulin (1992) in ours to elicit this prole as well.

5

It will be clear from the proof of our results, that if the planner wishes to include the cost prole c in α, α

i

(.) must be non-decreasing in c

i

to maintain the strategic properties of the procedure. If the planner wishes the outcome of the mechanism to also be immune to coalitional deviations, then α

i

(.) should not depend on the costs of other communities, c

−i

.

6

Many well-known rules meeting such a requirement exist (see, e.g., Moulin, 2002).

(9)

3 The Mechanism

Our mechanism proceeds in two stages after the planner announces the value of P

N b i . Stage 1: Each community i is asked to announce the lowest hosting cost among communities other than itself (i.e., communities in N \{i} ) 7 : c i . Dene c = min(c i ) . A community which announces c will be referred to as community i (the "optimist").

If there are more than one "optimist" then any tie-breaking rule can be applied to select i . If P

N b i c , proceed to Stage 2, otherwise stop and the project is not carried out.

Stage 2: Each community other than i is asked to announce its own hosting cost: γ i . Dene γ h = min i6=i

i ) . The host community (" h ") will be randomly chosen among those announcing γ h .

If P

N b i min γ j , the following transfers are implemented:

 

t h = −c + α h (θ)c

t i = α i (θ)c for i 6= h

If P

N b i < min γ j , the optimist becomes the host ( i = h ) and the above transfers are carried out.

The intuition is very simple: communities jointly propose a monetary compensa- tion for the host, c , which any community can acceptthus becoming the hostor reject. If no community accepts the compensation, the most fervent proponent of the project (the "optimist") is selected to be the host instead. This Divide and Choose

7

We consider that announcements are made in the smallest monetary unit available (e.g. 1 cent).

(10)

structure guarantees truthful revelation from the optimist.

Thus, if the project is carried out the payo of each community is:

 

u h = b h α h (θ)c + (c c h ) u i = b i α i (θ)c for i 6= h

Theorem 1. If b i α i (θ)c 1 0 for all i , the unique subgame perfect Nash equilibrium outcome of the mechanism coincides with truthful revelation, γ h = c = c 1 , whenever it is ecient to carry out the project. Otherwise the project is not carried out. The outcome is ecient, budget-balanced and individually rational.

Proof. We proceed by determining the best responses for all agents i 6= i in stage 2, and show that, given these best responses, all agents i 6= 1 announce c i = c 1 in stage 1.

Stage 2 : Best responses for i 6= i

Case 1: if c > c i ,

a) If min j6=i γ j > c i : Announce γ i = c i (or anything lower than min j6=i γ j in order to become the host).

b) Alternatively, if c i > min j6=i γ j : Announce γ i = min j6=i γ j 1 c/ (or any- thing lower so as to become the host).

Case 2: if c < c i : Announce γ i = P

N b j + 1 c/ (or anything higher so as to not become the host).

Case 3: if c = c i ,

a) If min j6=i γ j c i : Announce γ i = c i or anything else (agent i can do no

better than by announcing γ i = c i ) .

(11)

b) If min j6=i γ j > c i : Agent i can do no better than by announcing γ i = c i in this case also. Note that agent i 's payo would be equivalent if he announced γ i > min j6=i γ j , which would make another agent the host. However, given cases 1 and 2, such a situation cannot be part of a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium of our mechanism.

Stage 1 :

Best responses for i such that c i > c 1

If min j6=i c j > c 1 : Announce c i = c 1 , in order to become the optimist and pay a lower cost share (recall that c = min j c j becomes the cost in stage 2)

If min j6=i c j < c 1 : Announce c i = c 1 , in order to not become the optimist and, in turn, avoid becoming the host given the best response prole in stage 2.

If min j6=i c j = c 1 : Agent i can do no better than announcing c i = c 1 given the best response prole in stage 2.

Best responses for each agent i such that c i = c 1

Announce c i > c 1 so as to possibly become the host in stage 2 given the best responses.

We leave it to the reader to check that γ h = c = c 1 is indeed the unique SPNE outcome.

Hence, the unique SPNE outcome exists and coincides with truth-telling: when-

ever it is ecient to build, the project is carried out, the host is an ecient one, and

the cost to be shared is the true cost. An important concern regarding the selection of

an ecient outcome is its robustness to coalitional deviations, especially in a context

of possible proximity of agents (e.g. neighboring communities) which is consistent

(12)

their aggregate payo by joint deviations from the equilibrium, its stability could be compromised. It turns out that the unique SPNE outcome of our mechanism is also immune to coalitional deviations.

Theorem 2. The unique subgame perfect Nash equilibrium outcome of the mechanism is immune to coalitional deviations.

Proof. We denote by ∆x the variation of a variable x ; recall that b , θ and α are exogenously given. Denote by S N a deviating coalition.

Step 1: The grand coalition: S = N

The unique SPNE outcome of our mechanism is ecient: the host is one of the communities with the lowest cost, which maximizes the sum of all payos. Thus, the grand coalition cannot increase its aggregate payo by a joint deviation.

Step 2: h S .

Consider the joint payo:

X

S

u ih , c) = X

S

b i X

S

α i (θ)c + (c c h )

A positive variation in γ h (so that h is still the host) does not change the joint payo. If γ h + ∆γ h > min j6=h γ j , roles changes ( h "becomes" an agent i ) and the joint payo does not change. A negative variation in γ h does not change the joint payo either.

A negative variation in c decreases the payo by (1 P

S α i (θ))|∆c| > 0 . A positive variation is impossible given the best responses: all other communities announce c i = c 1 in the rst stage.

Coordinated deviations from c and γ h : if the variations are in opposite directions (positive for γ h and negative for c) or both negative the payo decreases in either case by (1 P

S α i (θ))|∆c| ≥ 0 .

(13)

Thus, P

S u ih , c) P

S u ih + ∆γ h , c + ∆c ) for any admissible values of ∆c and ∆γ h .

Step 3: h / S .

Clearly, variations not including h cannot be protable for the member of S because the only payo-altering deviation would be an inecient one where an agent in S becomes the host, which cannot increase the aggregate payo of coalition S .

Note that our results do not require agents to know the identity of the ecient host because the mechanism gives the ecient host incentives to reveal itself. However, in an informational context where the identity of the ecient host is known to the agents, the following simpler variant of our mechanism could be used: in the rst stage, all agents propose the identity of a host in addition to proposing a compensation.

The "optimist" is still selected among the ones which have announced the lowest compensation, c . In stage 2, the agent designated by the optimist can accept to be the host and receive the optimist's proposed compensation, or refuse in which case the optimist becomes the host with its own announcement as a compensation. The Divide and Choose structure is even clearer in this variant but requires slightly more information. All the desirable properties of the equilibrium outcome are preserved.

4 Conclusion

We developed a simple and general mechanism in the same vein as the Divide and

Choose method to select a host for a project generating local externalities. Our mech-

anism allows one to select an ecient site and to implement multiple redistribution

schemes. To the best of our knowledge, it is the rst mechanism to achieve both

(14)

objectives. It is simple and its unique subgame perfect Nash equilibrium outcome co- incides with truth-telling, is ecient, budget-balanced and immune to any coalitional deviations. Regarding the informational structure, it requires that each community knows the community with the lowest cost. This assumption, while restrictive, rea- sonably approximates environments where the involved agents have much more infor- mation about their respective characteristics than the planner (i.e., communities in a given region are typically better informed about their mutual characteristics than the federal state). Moreover, our mechanism can even be used to handle cases where communities disagree about the usefulness of the project (regradless of its location).

In a companion paper, Laurent-Lucchetti and Leroux (2008) propose a specic distribution of costs, α i (.) , based on normative considerations. At the heart of the argument is the mitigation of the physical asymmetry of the siting problem: the fact that the cost incurred by a single community (the host) determines the cost to be shared by all. This approach characterize a unique sharing rule which turns out to be the Lindahl Pricing method.

Our model could be extended by allowing for the disutility of other communities

than the host to be positive (e.g the neighbors of the host could also suer a disu-

tility). We chose not to address this possibility in the present model, implying that

communities are dened in a wide enough sense so that the externalities generated

by the project stay contained in it. Nonetheless, the question is an interesting one,

which we leave for further research.

(15)

References

[1] D'Aspremont, C. and L. Gerard-Varey. 1979. On Bayesian incentive compatible mechanisms, in "Aggregation and Revelation of Preferences. (J. J. Laont, Ed.), North-Holland, Amsterdam.

[2] Easterling, Douglas. 1992. "Fair Rules for Siting a High-Level Nuclear Waste Repository." Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 11, 442-475.

[3] Ehlers, Lars. 2008. "Choosing Wisely: The Natural Multi-Bidding Mechanism."

Economic Theory, forthcoming.

[4] Frey, Bruno S., Felix Oberholzer-Gee, and Reiner Eichenberger. 1996. "The Old Lady Visits Your Backyard: A Tale of Morals and Mar." The Journal of Political Economy, 104, 1297-1313.

[5] Gerrard, Michael B. 1994. Whose Backyard, Whose Risk: Fear and Fairness in Toxic and Nuclear Waste Siting. The MIT Press.

[6] Green, J. and J.J. Laont. 1979. Incentives in Public Decision Making. (J. J.

Laont, Ed.), North-Holland, Amsterdam.

[7] Jackson, M. 2001. "A crash course in implementation theory." Social Choice and Welfare, 18, 655-708.

[8] Jackson, Matthew, and Hervé Moulin. 1992. "Implementing a Public Project and Distributing its Cost." Journal of Economic Theory, 57(1), 125-140.

[9] Jehiel, Philippe, Benny Moldonavu, and Ennio Stacchetti. 1996. "How (Not) to Sell Nuclear Weapons." American Economic Review, 86(4), 814-29.

[10] Kunreuther, H., and P. Kleindorfer. 1986. "A sealed-bid auction mechanism for

siting noxious facilities." American Economic Review, 76, 295-299.

(16)

[11] Kunreuther, H., J. Linneroth-Bayer, and K. Fitzgerald. 1994. Siting Hazardous Facilities: Lessons from Europe and America., The Wharton Risk Management and Decision Processes Center, Working Paper no 94-08-22.

[12] Laurent-Lucchetti, Jérémy, and Justin Leroux. 2007. "Why me?: Siting a Locally Unwanted Public Good." mimeo, HEC Montréal.

[13] Mailath, G and A. Postlewaith, 1990. "Asymmetric information bargaining prob- lems with many agents." Review of Economic Studies, 57, issue 3, 351-67.

[14] Maskin, Eric, 1999. "Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality" Review of Eco- nomic Studies, 66, 23-38.

[15] Minehart, Deborah and Zvika Neeman. 2002. "Eective Siting of Waste Treat- ment Facilities." Journal of Environmental Economic and Management, 43, 303- 324.

[16] Moulin, Hervé. 2002. Axiomatic Cost and Surplus Sharing. Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, Elsevier Science.

[17] Moulin, Hervé. 2007. "Auctioning or assigning an object: some remarkable VCG mechanisms." mimeo, Rice University.

[18] O'Sullivan, A.1993. "Voluntary Auctions for Noxious Facilities: Incentives to Participate and the Eciency of Siting Decisions." Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 25, 12-26.

[19] Peleg, B. 1978. "Consistent voting systems." Econometrica, 46, 153-161.

[20] Perez-Castrillo, David, and David Wettstein. 2002. "Choosing Wisely: A Multi-

bidding Approach." The American Economic Review, 92, no 5., 1577-1587.

(17)

[21] Sullivan, Arthur M. 1990. "Victim Compensation Revisited: Eciency versus Equity in the Siting of Noxious Facilities." Journal of Public Economics, 41:

211-225.

[22] Sullivan, Arthur M.1992. "Siting Noxious Facilities: A Siting Lottery with Victim

Compensation." Journal of Urban Economics, 31: 360-374.

Références

Documents relatifs

The Report of the Committee to the General Assembly would be presented by the Chairperson of the twelfth session of the Intergovernmental Committee, H.E.

Further recalling that the Intergovernmental Committee for the Safeguarding of the Intangible Cultural Heritage, in its Decision 6.COM 22, decided that category

Noting the report of the Director-General 2 on assistance to the Republic of the Congo (Leopoldville) including inter alia the requests addressed to the Director-General by

Unlike the other approaches, which focus on one dimension (psychological or social) and thus reduce the complexity, the underlying assumption of our ECS method is that the better

b) Para piscinas com válvulas de admissão e retorno, o nível da água deve de estar a 20 cm do borde superior da piscina; fechar as válvulas com o sistema de rosca de que estão

Esta posibilidad se emplea para revolver el agua si debe añadirse un producto en la piscina o si se debe efectuar alguna operación en el filtro, dado que en este caso el filtro

These results show that a relevant method to correct the effect of imperfect spherical indenter geometry on the F-h curve is to consider the equality of mean contact

b) Para piscinas com válvulas de admissão e retorno, o nível da água deve de estar a 20 cm do borde superior da piscina; fechar as válvulas com o sistema de rosca de que estão