• Aucun résultat trouvé

On the connection between probability boxes and possibility measures

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "On the connection between probability boxes and possibility measures"

Copied!
28
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-00765618

https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00765618

Submitted on 15 Dec 2012

HAL

is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers.

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire

HAL, est

destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés.

On the connection between probability boxes and possibility measures

Matthias Troffaes, Enrique Miranda, Sébastien Destercke

To cite this version:

Matthias Troffaes, Enrique Miranda, Sébastien Destercke. On the connection between proba- bility boxes and possibility measures. Information Sciences, Elsevier, 2013, 224 (1), pp.88-108.

�10.1016/j.ins.2012.09.033�. �hal-00765618�

(2)

POSSIBILITY MEASURES

MATTHIAS C. M. TROFFAES, ENRIQUE MIRANDA, AND SEBASTIEN DESTERCKE

ABSTRACT. We explore the relationship between possibility measures (supremum pre- serving normed measures) and p-boxes (pairs of cumulative distribution functions) on to- tally preordered spaces, extending earlier work in this direction by De Cooman and Aeyels, among others. We start by demonstrating that only those p-boxes who have 0–1-valued lower or upper cumulative distribution function can be possibility measures, and we derive expressions for their natural extension in this case. Next, we establish necessary and suffi- cient conditions for a p-box to be a possibility measure. Finally, we show that almost every possibility measure can be modelled by a p-box, simply by ordering elements by increas- ing possibility. Whence, any techniques for p-boxes can be readily applied to possibility measures. We demonstrate this by deriving joint possibility measures from marginals, un- der varying assumptions of independence, using a technique known for p-boxes. Doing so, we arrive at a new rule of combination for possibility measures, for the independent case.

1. INTRODUCTION

Firstly, possibility measures are supremum preserving set functions, and were intro- duced in fuzzy set theory [39], although earlier appearances exist [28, 20]. Because of their computational simplicity, possibility measures are widely applied in many fields, in- cluding data analysis [32], diagnosis [4], cased-based reasoning [18], and psychology [27].

This paper concerns quantitative possibility theory [13], where degrees of possibility range in the unit interval. Interpretations abound [11]: we can see them as likelihood functions [12], as particular cases of plausibility measures [29, 30], as extreme probability distribu- tions [31], or as upper probabilities [37, 6]. The upper probability interpretation fits our purpose best, whence is assumed herein.

Secondly, probability boxes [14, 15], or p-boxes for short, are pairs of lower and upper cumulative distribution functions, and are often used in risk and safety studies, in which they play an essential role. P-boxes have been connected to info-gap theory [16], random sets [19, 26], and also, partly, to possibility measures [1, 6]. P-boxes can be defined on ar- bitrary finite spaces [9], and, more generally, even on arbitrarily totally pre-ordered spaces [34]—we will use this extensively.

This paper aims to consolidate the connection between possibility measures and p- boxes, making as few assumptions as possible. We prove that almost every possibility measure can be interpreted as a p-box, simply by ordering elements by increasing possibil- ity, whence, p-boxes effectively generalize possibility measures. Conversely, we provide necessary and sufficient conditions for a p-box to be a possibility measure, whence, pro- viding conditions under which the more efficient mathematical machinery of possibility measures is applicable to p-boxes.

Key words and phrases. Probability boxes, possibility measures, maxitive measures, coherent lower and up- per probabilities, natural extension.

1

(3)

To study this connection, we use imprecise probabilities [36], because both possibility measures and p-boxes are particular cases of imprecise probabilities. Possibility measures are explored as imprecise probabilities in [37, 6, 23], and p-boxes were studied as imprecise probabilities briefly in [36, Section 4.6.6] and [33], and in much more detail in [34].

The paper is organised as follows: in Section 2, we give the basics of the behavioural theory of imprecise probabilities, and recall some facts about p-boxes and possibility mea- sures; in Section 3, we first determine necessary and sufficient conditions for a p-box to be maximum preserving, before determining in Section 4 necessary and sufficient conditions for a p-box to be a possibility measure; in Section 5, we show that almost any possibility measure can be seen as particular p-box, and that many p-boxes can be seen as a couple of possibility measures; some special cases are detailed in Section 6. Finally, in Section 7 we apply the work on multivariate p-boxes from [34] to derive multivariate possibility mea- sures from given marginals, and in Section 8 we give a number of additional comments and remarks.

2. PRELIMINARIES

2.1. Imprecise Probabilities. We start with a brief introduction to imprecise probabilities (see [2, 38, 36, 22] for more details). Because possibility measures are interpretable as upper probabilities, we start out with those, instead of lower probabilities—the resulting theory is equivalent.

LetΩbe the possibility space. A subset ofΩis called anevent. Denote the set of all events by℘pΩq, and the set of all finitely additive probabilities on℘pΩqbyP.

In this paper, anupper probabilityis any real-valued functionPdefined on an arbitrary subsetK of℘pΩq. WithP, we associate alower probability PontA: AcPKuvia the conjugacy relationship

PpAq “1´PpAcq.

Denote the set of all finitely additive probabilities on℘pΩqthat are dominated byPby:

MpPq “ tPPP:p@APKqpPpAq ďPpAqqu

Clearly,MpPqis also the set of all finitely additive probabilities on℘pΩqthat dominateP on its domaintA:AcPKu.

The upper envelopeEofMpPqis called thenatural extension[36, Thm. 3.4.1] ofP:

EpAq “suptPpAq:PPMpPqu

for allAĎΩ. The corresponding lower probability is denoted byE, soEpAq “1´EpAcq.

Clearly,Eis the lower envelope ofMpPq.

We say thatPiscoherent(see [36, p. 134, Sec. 3.3.3]) when it coincides withEon its domain, that is, when, for allAPK,

PpAq “EpAq.

The lower probabilityPis calledcoherentwheneverPis.

The upper envelope of any set of finitely additive probabilities on℘pΩqis coherent. A coherent upper probabilityPand its conjugate lower probability Psatisfy the following properties [36, Sec. 2.7.4], whenever the relevant events belong to their domain:

(1) 0ďPpAq ďPpAq ď1.

(2) AĎBimpliesPpAq ďPpBqandPpAq ďPpBq. [Monotonicity]

(3) PpAYBq ďPpAq `PpBq. [Subadditivity]

(4)

1 Ω 0

1

F F

FIGURE1. Example of a p-box onr0,1s.

2.2. P-Boxes. In this section, we revise the theory and some of the main results for p- boxes defined on totally preordered (not necessarily finite) spaces. For further details, we refer to [34].

We start with a totally preordered spacepΩ,ĺq. So,ĺis transitive and reflexive and any two elements are comparable. As usual, we writexăyforxĺyandxy,xąyfor yăx, andx»yforxĺyandyĺx. For any twox,yPΩexactly one ofxăy,x»y, or xąyholds. We also use the following common notation for intervals inΩ:

rx,ys “ tzPΩ:xĺzĺyu px,yq “ tzPΩ:xăzăyu and similarly forrx,yqandpx,ys.

We assume thatΩhas a smallest element 0 and a largest element 1. This is not an essential assumption, since we can always add these two elements to the spaceΩ.

Acumulative distribution functionis a non-decreasing mapF:ΩÑ r0,1sfor which Fp1q “1. For eachxPΩ,Fpxqis interpreted as the probability ofr0,xs. No further restrictions are imposed onF.

The quotient set ofΩwith respect to»is denoted byΩ{ »:

rxs»“ tyPΩ:y»xufor anyxPΩ Ω{ » “ trxs»:xPΩu.

BecauseF is non-decreasing,F is constant on elementsrxs» ofΩ{ »—we will use this repeatedly.

Definition 1. Aprobability box, orp-box, is a pairpF,Fqof cumulative distribution func- tions fromΩtor0,1ssatisfyingFďF.

A p-box is interpreted as a lower and an upper cumulative distribution function (see Fig. 1), or more specifically, as an upper probabilityPF,Fon the set of events

tr0,xs:xPΩu Y tpy,1s:yPΩu defined by

PF,Fpr0,xsq “FpxqandPF,Fppy,1sq “1´Fpyq. (1)

We denote byEF,Fthe natural extension ofPF,Fto all events.

We now recall the main results that we shall need regarding the natural extensionEF,F ofPF,F (see [34] for further details). First, becausePF,Fis coherent,EF,F coincides with PF,Fon its domain.

(5)

Next, to simplify the expression for natural extension, we introduce an element 0´ such that:

0´ăxfor allxPΩ Fp0´q “Fp0´q “Fp0´q “0.

Note thatp0´,xs “ r0,xs. Now, letΩ˚“ΩY t0´u, and define

H “ tpx0,x1s Y px2,x3s Y ¨ ¨ ¨ Y px2n,x2n`1s:x0ăx1㨠¨ ¨ăx2n`1inΩ˚u.

Proposition 2([34]). For any APH, that is A“ px0,x1s Y px2,x3s Y ¨ ¨ ¨ Y px2n,x2n`1swith x0ăx1㨠¨ ¨ăx2n`1inΩ˚, it holds that EF,FpAq “PHF,FpAq, where

PHF,FpAq “1´

n`1

ÿ

k0

maxt0,Fpx2kq ´Fpx2k´1qu, (2) with x´1“0´and x2n`2“1.

To calculateEF,FpAqfor an arbitrary eventAĎΩ, we can use the outer measure [36, Cor. 3.1.9,p. 127]PHF,F˚of the upper probabilityPHF,Fdefined in Eq. (2):

EF,FpAq “PHF,F˚pAq “ inf

CPH,AĎCPHF,FpCq. (3)

For intervals, we immediately infer from Proposition 2 and Eq. (3) that

EF,Fppx,ysq “Fpyq ´Fpxq (4a)

EF,Fprx,ysq “Fpyq ´Fpx´q (4b)

EF,Fppx,yqq “

#

Fpyq ´Fpxq ifyhas no immediate predecessor

Fpy´q ´Fpxq ifyhas an immediate predecessor (4c) EF,Fprx,yqq “

#

Fpyq ´Fpx´q ifyhas no immediate predecessor

Fpy´q ´Fpx´q ifyhas an immediate predecessor (4d) for anyxăyinΩ,1whereFpy´qdenotes supzăyFpzqand similarly forFpx´q. IfΩ{ » is finite, then one can think ofz´as the immediate predecessor ofzin the quotient space Ω{ »for anyzPΩ. Note that in particular

EF,Fptxuq “Fpxq ´Fpx´q (5)

for anyxPΩ. We will use this repeatedly.

2.3. Possibility and Maxitive Measures. Very briefly, we introduce possibility and max- itive measures. For further information, see [39, 13, 37, 6].

Definition 3. Amaxitive measure is an upper probability P:℘pΩq Ñ r0,1s satisfying PpAYBq “maxtPpAq,PpBqufor everyA,BĎΩ.

It follows from the above definition that a maxitive measure is also maximum-preserving when we consider finite unions of events.

The following result is well-known, but we include a quick proof for the sake of com- pleteness.

Proposition 4. A maxitive measure P is coherent whenever PpHq “0and PpΩq “1.

1In casex0, evidently, 0´is the immediate predecessor.

(6)

Proof. By [25, Theorem 1], a maxitive measurePsatisfyingPpHq “0 is8-alternating, and as a consequence also 2-alternating. Whence, P is coherent by [35, p. 55, Corol-

lary 6.3].

Possibility measures are a particular case of maxitive measures.

Definition 5. A (normed)possibility distributionis a mappingπ:ΩÑ r0,1ssatisfying supxPπpxq “1. A possibility distributionπ induces apossibility measureΠ on℘pΩq, given by:

ΠpAq “sup

xPA

πpxqfor allAĎΩ.

Equivalently, possibility measures can be defined as supremum-preserving upper prob- abilities, i.e., as functionalsΠfor which

ΠpYAPAAq “sup

APAΠpAq @A ĎPpΩq.

If we writeEΠfor the conjugate lower probability of the upper probabilityΠ, then:

EΠpAq “1´ΠpAcq “1´sup

xPAc

πpxq.

A possibility measure is maxitive, but not all maxitive measures are possibility mea- sures.

As an imprecise probability model, possibility measures are not as expressive as for instance p-boxes—for example, the only probability measures that can be represented by possibility measures are the degenerate ones. This poor expressive power is also illustrated by the fact that, for any eventA:

ΠpAq ă1 ùñ EΠpAq “0, and therefore EΠpAq ą0 ùñ ΠpAq “1,

meaning that every event has a trivial probability bound on at least one side. Their main at- traction is that calculations with them are very easy: to find the upper (or lower) probability of any event, a simple supremum suffices.

In the following sections, we characterize the circumstances under which a possibility measure Π is the natural extension of some p-box pF,Fq. In order to do so, we first characterise the conditions under which a p-box induces a maxitive measure.

3. P-BOXES ASMAXITIVEMEASURES.

We show here that p-boxespF,Fqon any totally preordered space where at least one of F orF is 0–1-valued are maxitive measures, and in this sense are closely related to possibility measures. We then derive a simple closed expression of the (upper) natural extension of such p-boxes.

3.1. A Necessary Condition for Maxitivity.

Proposition 6. If the natural extension EF,F of a p-boxpF,Fqis maximum preserving, then at least one of F or F is0–1-valued.

Proof. We begin by showing that there is noxPΩsuch that 0ăFpxq ďFpxq ă1. Assume ex absurdo that there is such anx. ForEF,F to be maximum preserving, we require that

EF,Fpr0,xs Y px,1sq “maxtEF,Fpr0,xsq,EF,Fppx,1squ

(7)

0

1 Ω 0

1

F F

A1 A2

B1 B2

FIGURE2. A p-box for the proof of Proposition 6.

But this cannot be. The left hand side is 1, whereas the right hand side is strictly less than one, because, by Eq. (1),

EF,Fpr0,xsq “Fpxq ă1, EF,Fppx,1sq “1´Fpxq ă1.

Whence, for everyxPΩ, at least one ofFpxq “0 orFpxq “1 must hold. In other words, Fpxq “0 wheneverFpxq ă1, andFpxq “1 wheneverFpxq ą0 (see Figure 2). Hence, the sets

A1:“ txPΩ:Fpxq ă1u A2:“ tyPΩ:Fpyq ą0u

are disjoint, and A1ăA2 in the sense thatxăy for all xPA1 andyPA2. Indeed, if xPA1andyPA2, thenFpxq ă1, andFpyq “1 becauseFpyq ą0. These can only hold simultaneously ifxăy.

Note thatA1is empty whenFpxq “1 for allxPΩ, and in this case the desired result is trivially established.A2is non-empty becauseFp1q “1. Anyway, consider the sets

B1:“ txPΩ: 0ăFpxq ă1u ĎA1 B2:“ tyPΩ: 0ăFpyq ă1u ĎA2

The proposition is established if we can show that at least one of these two sets is empty.

Suppose, ex absurdo, that both are non-empty. Pick any elementcPB1anddPB2and consider the setC“ r0,cs Y pd,1s—note thatcădbecausecPA1anddPA2, sopc,ds is non-empty. Whence, by Eq. (2),

EF,Fpr0,cs Y pd,1sq “1´maxt0,Fpdq ´Fpcqu.

Also, by Eq. (1),

EF,Fpr0,csq “Fpcq, EF,Fppd,1sq “1´Fpdq.

(8)

So, forEF,F to be maximum preserving, we require that

1´maxt0,Fpdq ´Fpcqu “maxtFpcq,1´Fpdqu.

But this cannot hold. Indeed, because 0ăFpcq ă1 and 0ă1´Fpdq ă1, the above equality can only hold ifFpdq ´Fpcq ą0—otherwise the left hand side would be 1 whereas the right hand side is strictly less than 1. So, effectively, we require that

1´Fpdq `Fpcq “maxtFpcq,1´Fpdqu.

This cannot hold, because the sum of two strictly positive numbers (in this case 1´Fpdq andFpcq) is always strictly larger than their maximum. We conclude thatEF,F cannot be maximum preserving if bothB1andB2are non-empty. In other words, at least one ofFor

Fmust be 0–1-valued.

3.2. Sufficient Conditions for Maxitivity. We derive sufficient conditions for the two different cases described by Proposition 6, starting with 0–1-valuedF.

3.2.1. Maxitivity for Zero-One Valued Lower Cumulative Distribution Functions. We first provide a simple expression for the natural extension of such p-boxes over events.

Proposition 7. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box with0–1-valued F, and let B“ txPΩ˚: Fpxq “0u.

Then, for any AĎΩ, EF,FpAq “

#

infxP˚:AXBĺxFpxq if yăAXBcfor at least one yPBc,

1 otherwise. (6)

“min

yPBc inf

xP˚:AXr0,yx

Fpxq. (7)

In the above,Aĺxmeanszĺxfor allzPA, and similarlyyăAmeansyăzfor all zPA. For example, it holds thatHĺxandyăHfor allxandy.

Proof. We deduce from Eq. (3) and from the conjugacy betweenEF,F andEF,F that for anyAĎΩ,

EF,FpAq “ sup

px0,x1sY¨¨¨Ypx2n,x2n`1A n

ÿ

k0

maxt0,Fpx2k`1q ´Fpx2kqu.

All the terms in this sum are zero except possibly for one (if it exists) wherex2kPB,x2k`1P Bc, where we get 1´Fpx2kq. Aside, as subsets ofΩ˚, note that bothBandBc are non- empty: 0´ PBand 1PBc. Consequently,

EF,FpAq “1´ inf

x,y:xPB,yPBc,px,yAFpxq;

and therefore

EF,FpAq “ inf

x,y:xPB,yPBc,px,yAcFpxq

“ inf

x,y:xPB,yPBc,AĎr0,xsYpy,1s

Fpxq

where it is understood that the infimum evaluates to 1 whenever there are noxPBand yPBcsuch thatAĎ r0,xs Y py,1s.

Now, for anyxPBandyPBc, it holds thatAĎ r0,xs Y py,1sif and only if AXBĎ pr0,xs Y py,1sq XB“ r0,xsand

AXBcĎ pr0,xs Y py,1sq XBc“ py,1s,

(9)

that is, if and only if

AXBĺxandyăAXBc. Hence, if there is anyPBcsuch thatyăAXBc, then:

(i) either there is noxPBsuch thatAXBĺx, whence EF,FpAq “1“ inf

xP˚:AXBĺx

Fpxq,

taking into account that for anyxPΩ˚ such thatAXBĺxit must be thatxPBc, whenceFpxq “Fpxq “1;

(ii) or there is somexPBsuch thatAXBĺx, in which case EF,FpAq “ inf

xPB:AXBĺxFpxq “ inf

xP˚:AXBĺx

Fpxq, where the second equality follows from the monotonicity ofF. This establishes Eq. (6).

We now turn to proving Eq. (7). In caseyăAXBcfor at least oneyPBc, it follows that EF,FpAq “ inf

xP˚:AXBĺxFpxq

But in this case,AXB“AX r0,y1sfor anyy1PBcsuch thaty1ĺy, because

AX r0,y1s “AX r0,y1s X pBYBcq “ pAXBX r0,y1sq Y pAXBcX r0,y1sq “AXB asBX r0,y1s “BandAXBcX r0,y1s “ Hbecausey1ĺyandyăAXBc. So, by the monotonicity ofF, Eq. (7) follows.

In casey⊀AXBcfor allyPBc, it follows that EF,FpAq “1“Fpxq

for all xinBc—indeed, becauseAX r0,ys XBc‰ Hfor every yPBc, it holds thatAX r0,ysĺximpliesxPBc, and henceFpxq “1. Again, Eq. (7) follows.

A few common important special cases are summarized in the following corollary:

Corollary 8. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box with0–1-valued F, and let B“ txPΩ˚: Fpxq “0u.

IfΩ{ »is order complete, then, for any AĎΩ, EF,FpAq “min

yPBcFpsupAX r0,ysq.

If, in addition, Bchas a minimum, then

EF,FpAq “FpsupAX r0,minBcsq. (8) If, in addition, Bc“ r1s»(this occurs exactly when F is vacuous, i.e. F“Ir1

s»), then

EF,FpAq “FpsupAq. (9)

Note that Eq. (9) is essentially due to [6, paragraph preceeding Theorem 11]—they work with chains and multivalued mappings, whereas we work with total preorders. We are now ready to show that the considered p-boxes are maxitive measures.

Proposition 9. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box where F is 0–1-valued. Then EF,F is maximum- preserving.

(10)

Proof. Consider a finite collectionA of subsets ofΩ. If there areAPA such that, for all yPBc,y⊀AXBc, thenEF,FpAq “1“EF,FpYAPAAqby Eq. (6), establishing the desired result for this case.

So, from now on, we may assume that, for everyAPA, there is ayAPBcsuch that yAăAXBc. Withy“minAPAyAPBc, it holds thatyăYAPAAXBc, and so, by Eq. (6),

EF,FpAq “ inf

xP˚:AXBĺxFpxqfor everyAPA,and EF,FpYAPAAq “ inf

xP˚:YAPAAXBĺxFpxq.

Now, becauseA is finite, there is anA1PA such that

txPΩ˚:A1XBĺxu “ XAPAtxPΩ˚: AXBĺxu and becauseYAPAAXBĺxif and only ifAXBĺxfor allAPA,

“ txPΩ˚: YAPA AXBĺxu.

Consequently, max

APAEF,FpAq “max

APA inf

xP˚:AXBĺxFpxq

ě inf

xP˚:A1XBĺxFpxq “ inf

xP˚:YAPAAXBĺxFpxq “EF,FpYAPAAq.

The converse inequality follows from the coherence ofEF,F. Concluding, max

APAEF,FpAq “EF,FpYAPAAq

for any finite collectionA of subsets ofΩ.

3.2.2. Maxitivity for Zero-One Valued Upper Cumulative Distribution Functions. Let us now consider the case of 0–1-valuedF.

Proposition 10. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box with0–1-valued F, and let C“ txPΩ˚:Fpxq “0u.

Then, for any AĎΩ, EF,FpAq “

#

1´supyP˚:yăAXCcFpyq if AXCĺx for at least one xPC,

1 otherwise. (10)

“1´max

xPC sup

yP˚:yăAXpx,1s

Fpyq. (11)

Proof. We deduce from Eq. (3) and from the conjugacy betweenEF,F andEF,F that for anyAĎΩ,

EF,FpAq “ sup

px0,x1sY¨¨¨Ypx2n,x2n`1A

ÿn

k0

maxt0,Fpx2k`1q ´Fpx2kqu.

All the terms in this sum are zero except possibly for one (if it exists) wherex2kPC,x2k`1P Cc, where we getFpx2k`1q. Aside, as subsets ofΩ˚, note that bothCandCc are non- empty: 0´ PCand 1PCc. Consequently,

EF,FpAq “ sup

x,y:xPC,yPCc,px,yA

Fpyq;

(11)

and therefore

EF,FpAq “1´ sup

x,y:xPC,yPCc,px,yAc

Fpyq

“1´ sup

x,y:xPC,yPCc,AĎr0,xsYpy,1s

Fpyq

where it is understood that the supremum evaluates to 0 whenever there are noxPCand yPCcsuch thatAĎ r0,xs Y py,1s.

Now, for anyxPCandyPCc, it holds thatAĎ r0,xs Y py,1sif and only if AXCĎ pr0,xs Y py,1sq XC“ r0,xsand

AXCcĎ pr0,xs Y py,1sq XCc“ py,1s, that is, if and only if

AXCĺxandyăAXCc. Hence, if there is anxPCsuch thatAXCĺx, then:

(i) either there is noyPCcsuch thatyăAXCc, whence EF,FpAq “1“1´ sup

yP˚:yăAXCc

Fpyq,

taking into account that for anyyPΩ˚such thatyăAXCc it must be thatyPC, whenceFpyq “Fpyq “0;

(ii) or there is someyPCcsuch thatyăAXCc, in which case EF,FpAq “1´ sup

yPCc:yăAXCc

Fpyq “1´ sup

yP˚:yăAXCc

Fpyq, where the second equality follows from the monotonicity ofF. This establishes Eq. (10).

We now turn to proving Eq. (11). In caseAXCĺxfor at least onexPC, it follows that EF,FpAq “1´ sup

yP˚:yăAXCc

Fpyq.

But in this case,AXCc“AX px1,1sfor anyx1PCsuch thatx1ľx, because

AX px1,1s “AX px1,1s X pCYCcq “ pAXCX px1,1sq Y pAXCcX px1,1sq “AXCc asCcX px1,1s “CcandAXCX px1,1s “ Hby assumption. So, by the monotonicity of F, Eq. (11) follows.

In caseAXCxfor allxPC, it follows that

EF,FpAq “1“1´Fpyq

for ally inC—indeed, becauseAX px,1s XC‰ Hfor everyxPC, it holds thatyă AX px,1simpliesyPC, and henceFpyq “0. Again, Eq. (11) follows.

A few common important special cases are summarized in the following corollary:

Corollary 11. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box with0–1-valued F, and let C“ txPΩ˚:Fpxq “0u.

IfΩ{ »is order complete, and C has a maximum, then, for any AĎΩ, EF,FpAq “

#

1´FpinfAXCcq if AXCchas no minimum

1´FppminAXCcq´q if AXCchas a minimum. (12)

(12)

If, in addition, C“ t0´u(this occurs exactly when F is vacuous, i.e. F“1), then EF,FpAq “

#

1´FpinfAq if A has no minimum 1´FpminA´q if A has a minimum.

Proof. Use Proposition 10, and note thatpmaxC,1s “Cc. Using Eq. (10), we can also show thatEF,F is maximum-preserving whenF is 0–1- valued:

Proposition 12. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box where F is0–1-valued. Then EF,F is maximum- preserving.

Proof. Consider a finite collectionA of subsets ofΩ. If there areAPA such that, for all xPC,AXCx, thenEF,FpAq “1“EF,FpYAPAAqby Eq. (10), establishing the desired result for this case.

So, from now on, we may assume that, for everyAPA, there is anxAPCsuch that AXCĺxA. Withx“maxAPAxAPC, it holds thatYAPAAXCĺx, and so, by Eq. (10),

EF,FpAq “1´ sup

yP˚:yăAXCc

Fpyqfor everyAPA,and EF,FpYAPAAq “1´ sup

yP˚:yăYAPAAXCc

Fpyq.

Now, becauseA is finite, there is anA1PA such that

tyPΩ˚:yăA1XCcu “ XAPAtyPΩ˚: yăAXCcu and becauseyăYAPAAXCcif and only ifyăAXCcfor allAPA,

“ tyPΩ˚:yăYAPAAXCcu.

Consequently, max

APAEF,FpAq “max

APA

˜

1´ sup

yP˚:yăAXCc

Fpyq

¸

ě1´ sup

yP˚:yăA1XCc

Fpyq “1´ sup

yP˚:yăYAPAAXCc

Fpyq “EF,FpYAPAAq.

The converse inequality follows from the coherence ofEF,F. Concluding, max

APAEF,FpAq “EF,FpYAPAAq

for any finite collectionA of subsets ofΩ.

3.3. Summary of Necessary and Sufficient Conditions. Putting Propositions 6, 9 and 12 together, we get the following conditions.

Corollary 13. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box. Then,pF,Fqis maximum-preserving if and only if F is0–1-valued

or

F is0–1-valued.

These simple conditions characterise maximum-preserving p-boxes and bring us closer to p-boxes that are possibility measures, and that we will now study.

(13)

4. P-BOXES ASPOSSIBILITYMEASURES.

In this section, we identify when p-boxes coincide exactly with a possibility measure.

By Corollary 13, whenΩ{ »is finite,pF,Fqis a possibility measure if and only if eitherF orFis 0–1-valued. More generally, whenΩ{ »is not finite, we will rely on the following trivial, yet important, lemma:

Lemma 14. For a p-boxpF,Fqthere is a possibility measureΠsuch that EF,F“Πif and only if

EF,FpAq “sup

xPA

EF,Fptxuqfor all AĎΩ (13) and in such a case, the possibility distributionπassociated withΠisπpxq “EF,Fptxuq.

Proof. “if”. IfEF,FpAq “supxPAEF,Fptxuqfor allAĎΩ, thenEF,F“EΠ with the sug- gested choice ofπ, because, for allAĎΩ,

EF,FpAq “1´EF,FpAcq “1´sup

xPAc

EF,Fptxuq “1´sup

xPAc

πpxq “1´ΠpAcq “EΠpAq.

“only if”. IfEF,F“EΠ, then, for allAĎΩ, EF,FpAq “ΠpAq “sup

xPA

πpxq “sup

xPA

Πptxuq “sup

xPA

EF,Fptxuq.

We will say thata p-boxpF,Fqis a possibility measurewhenever Eq. (13) is satisfied.

Note that, due to Proposition 6, for a p-box to be a possibility measure, at least one ofF orFmust be 0–1-valued. Next, we give a characterisation of p-boxes inducing a possibility measure in each of these two cases.

4.1. P-Boxes with Zero-One-Valued Lower Cumulative Distribution Functions. As mentioned, by Corollary 13, a p-box with 0–1-valuedF is maxitive, and its upper natural extension is given by Proposition 7. Whence, we can easily determine when such p-box is a possibility measure:

Proposition 15. Assume thatΩ{ »is order complete. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box with 0–1- valued F, and let B“ txPΩ˚: Fpxq “0u. Then,pF,Fqis a possibility measure if and only if

(i) Fpxq “Fpx´qfor all xPΩthat have no immediate predecessor, and (ii) Bchas a minimum,

and in such a case,

EF,FpAq “ sup

xPAXr0,minBcs

Fpxq (14)

Note that, in case 1 is a minimum ofBc, condition (i) is essentially due to [6, Ob- servation 9]. Also note that, forEF,F to be a possibility measure, both conditions are still necessary even whenΩ{ »is not order complete: the proof in this direction does not require order completeness.

As a special case, we mention thatEF,Fis a possibility measure with possibility distri- bution

πpxq “

#

Fpxq ifxĺminBc 0 otherwise.

wheneverΩ{ »is finite.

(14)

Proof. “only if”. Assume thatpF,Fqis a possibility measure. For everyxPΩthat has no immediate predecessor,

Fpx´q “sup

x1ăx

Fpx1q and becauseEF,Fptx1uq “Fpx1q ´Fpx1´q(see Eq. (5)),

ěsup

x1ăx

EF,Fptx1uq and becausepF,Fqis a possibility measure, by Lemma 14,

“EF,Fpr0,xqq “Fpxq

using thatxhas no immediate predecessor and Eqs. (4). The converse inequality follows from the non-decreasingness ofF.

Next, assume that, ex absurdo,Bc“ txPΩ˚:Fpxq “1uhas no minimum. This simply means that for everyxPBcthere is anx1PBcsuch thatx1ăx. So, in particular,Fpxq “ Fpx´q “1 for allxinBc, and hence,

EF,FpBcq “sup

xPBc

EF,Fptxuq “sup

xPBc

pFpxq ´Fpx´qq “0.

Yet, also,

EF,FpBcq “1 by Eq. (6). We arrived at a contradiction.

Finally, we show that Eq. (14) holds. By Eq. (7), EF,FpAq “min

yPBc inf

xP˚:AXr0,yxFpxq “ inf

xP˚:AXr0,minBcxFpxq “EF,FpA1q, withA1:“AX r0,minBcs. SinceEF,Fis a possibility measure, we conclude that

EF,FpAq “EF,FpA1q “sup

xPA1

EF,Fptxuq “sup

xPA1

Fpxq,

becauseEF,Fptxuq “Fpxq ´Fpx´q “Fpxq, sinceFpx´q “0 for allxP r0,minBcs. Hence, Eq. (14) holds.

“if”. The claim is established if we can show that Eq. (14) holds, because then EF,FpAq “ sup

xPAXr0,minBcs

Fpxq “ sup

xPAXr0,minBcs

EF,Fptxuqĺsup

xPA

EF,Fptxuq, and the converse inequality follows from the monotonicity ofEF,F.

Consider any eventAĎΩ, and letybe a supremum ofA1“AX r0,minBcs(which ex- ists becauseΩ{ »is order complete), soEF,FpAq “Fpyqby Eq. (8). Ifyhas an immediate predecessor, thenA1has a maximum (as we will show next), and

EF,FpAq “Fpyq “FpmaxA1q “max

xPA1

Fpxq “sup

xPA1

Fpxq.

Ifyhas no immediate predecessor, then eitherA1has a maximum, and the above argument can be recycled, orA1has no maximum, in which case

EF,FpAq “Fpyq “Fpy´q “sup

xPA1

Fpxq.

The last equality holds because

Fpy´q “ sup

xăsupA1

Fpxq

(15)

and,A1has no maximum, so for everyxăsupA1, there is anx1PA1such thatxăx1ăsupA1, whence

“sup

x1PA1

Fpx1q.

We are left to prove A1 has a maximum whenever y has an immediate predecessor.

Suppose thatA1has no maximum. Then it must hold that xăyfor allxPA1

since otherwisex»yfor somexPA1, wherebyxwould be a maximum ofA1. But, sinceyhas an immediate predecessory´, the above equation implies that

xĺy´for allxPA1.

Hence, y´is an upper bound forA1, yet y´ăy: this implies that yis not a minimal upper bound for A1, or in other words, thatyis not a supremum of A1: we arrived at a

contradiction. We conclude thatA1must have a maximum.

4.2. P-Boxes with Zero-One-Valued Upper Cumulative Distribution Functions. Sim- ilarly, we can also determine when a p-box with 0–1-valuedFis a possibility measure:

Proposition 16. Assume thatΩ{ »is order complete. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box with 0–1- valued F, and let C“ txPΩ˚:Fpxq “0u. Then, pF,Fqis a possibility measure if and only if

(i) Fpxq “Fpx`qfor all xPΩthat have no immediate successor, and (ii) C has a maximum,

and in such a case,

EF,FpAq “1´ inf

yPAXCcFpy´q. (15)

Again, for EF,F to be a possibility measure, both conditions are still necessary even whenΩ{ »is not order complete: the proof in this direction does not require order com- pleteness.

As a special case, we mention thatEF,Fis a possibility measure with possibility distri- bution

πpxq “

#

1´Fpx´q ifxPCc

0 otherwise,

wheneverΩ{ »is finite.

Proof. “only if”. Assume thatpF,Fqis a possibility measure. For everyxPΩthat has no immediate successor,

Fpx`q “ inf

x1ąxFpx1q “ inf

x1ąxFpx1´q

where the latter equality holds because for everyx1ąxthere is anx2such thatx1ąx2ąx;

otherwise, xwould have an immediate successor. Now, because EF,Fptx1uq “Fpx1q ´ Fpx1´q(see Eq. (5)),Fpx1´q ď1´EF,Fptx1uq, whence

ď inf

x1ąxp1´EF,Fptx1uqq “1´sup

x1ąx

EF,Fptx1uq and becausepF,Fqis a possibility measure, by Lemma 14,

“1´EF,Fppx,1sq “Fpxq,

(16)

where last equality follows from Eq. (1). The converse inequality follows from the non- decreasingness ofF.

Next, assume that, ex absurdo,C“ txPΩ˚:Fpxq “0uhas no maximum. SinceFpxq “ Fpx´q “0 for allxinC,

EF,FpCq “sup

xPC

EF,Fptxuq “sup

xPC

pFpxq ´Fpx´qq “0.

Yet, also,

EF,FpCq “1

by Eq. (10)—indeed, the second case applies because there is noxPCsuch thatCĺx, as Chas no maximum. We arrived at a contradiction.

Finally, we show that Eq. (15) holds. By Eq. (11), EF,FpAq “1´max

xPC sup

yP˚:yăAXpx,1s

Fpyq “1´ sup

yP˚:yăAXpmaxC,1s

Fpyq “EF,FpA1q, withA1:“AX pmaxC,1s “AXCc. SinceEF,F is a possibility measure, we conclude that

EF,FpAq “EF,FpA1q “sup

yPA1

EF,Fptyuq “sup

yPA1

p1´Fpy´qq “1´inf

yPA1Fpy´q, becauseEF,Fptyuq “Fpyq ´Fpy´q “1´Fpy´q, sinceFpyq “1 for allyPCc. Hence, Eq. (15) holds.

“if”. The claim is established if we can show that Eq. (15) holds, because then EF,FpAq “1´ inf

yPAXCcFpy´q “ sup

yPAXCc

p1´Fpy´qq ďsup

yPA

EF,Fptyuq, and the converse inequality follows from the monotonicity ofEF,F.

Consider any eventAĎΩ, and letxbe an infimum ofA1“AXCc(which exists because Ω{ »is order complete). Ifxhas an immediate successor, thenA1has a minimum (as we will show next), and by Eq. (12),

EF,FpAq “1´FpminA1´q “1´min

yPA1Fpy´q “1´inf

yPA1Fpy´q.

Ifxhas no immediate successor, then eitherA1 has a minimum, and the above argument can be recycled, orA1has no minimum, in which case Eq. (12) implies that

EF,FpAq “1´Fpxq “1´Fpx`q “1´inf

yPA1Fpy´q.

Here the second equality follows from assumption (i) and the last equality holds because Fpx`q “ inf

yąinfA1Fpyq

and,A1has no minimum, so for everyyąinfA1, there is ay1PΩsuch thatyąy1ąinfA1, whence

“ inf

yąinfA1 sup

yąy1ąinfA

Fpy1q “ inf

yąinfA1Fpy´q

and, again,A1has no minimum, so for everyyąinfA1, there is ay2PA1such thatyąy2ą infA1, whence

“ inf

y2PA1

Fpy2´q.

(17)

We are left to proveA1has a minimum wheneverxhas an immediate successor. Suppose thatA1has no minimum. Then it must hold that

yąxfor allyPA1

since otherwisey»xfor someyPA1, wherebyywould be a minimum ofA1. But, sincexhas an immediate successorx`, the above equation implies that

yľx`for allyPA1.

Hence,x`is a lower bound forA1, yetx`ąx: this implies thatxis not a maximal lower bound forA1, or in other words, thatxis not an infimum ofA1: we arrived at a contradiction.

We conclude thatA1must have a minimum.

4.3. Necessary and Sufficient Conditions. Merging Corollary 13 with Propositions 15 and 16 we obtain the following necessary and sufficient conditions for a p-box to be a possibility measure:

Corollary 17. Assume thatΩ{ »is order complete and letpF,Fqbe a p-box. ThenpF,Fq is a possibility measure if and only if either

(L1) F is0–1-valued,

(L2) Fpxq “Fpx´qfor all xPΩthat have no immediate predecessor, and (L3) txPΩ˚:Fpxq “1uhas a minimum,

or

(U1) F is0–1-valued,

(U2) Fpxq “Fpx`qfor all xPΩthat have no immediate successor, and (U3) txPΩ˚:Fpxq “0uhas a maximum.

This result settles the cases where p-boxes reduce to possibility measures. We can now go the other way around, and characterise those cases where possibility measures are p- boxes. Similarly to what happens in the finite setting, we will see that almost all possibility measures can be represented by a p-box.

5. FROMPOSSIBILITYMEASURES TOP-BOXES

In this section, we discuss and extend some previous results linking possibility distribu- tion to p-boxes. We show that possibility measures correspond to specific kinds of p-boxes, and that some p-boxes correspond to the conjunction of two possibility distribution.

5.1. Possibility Measures as Specific P-boxes. Baudrit and Dubois in [1] already discuss the link between possibility measures and p-boxes defined on the real line with the usual ordering, and they show that any possibility measure can be approximated by a p-box, however at the expense of losing some information. We substantially strengthen their result, and even reverse it: we prove that any possibility measure with compact range can beexactlyrepresented by a p-box with vacuous lower cumulative distribution function, that is,F“Ir1

s». In other words, generally speaking, possibility measures are a special case of p-boxes on totally preordered spaces.

Theorem 18. For every possibility measureΠ onΩ with possibility distributionπ such thatπpΩq “ tπpxq:xPΩuis compact, there is a preorderĺonΩand an upper cumulative distribution function F such that the p-boxpF “Ir1

s»,Fqis a possibility measure with possibility distributionπ, that is, such that for all events A:

EF,FpAq “sup

xPA

πpxq.

(18)

In fact, one may take the preorder ĺto be the one induced by π (so xĺy whenever πpxq ďπpyq) and F“π.

Proof. Let ĺ be the preorder induced by π. Order completeness of Ω{ »is satisfied becauseπpΩqis compact with respect to the usual topology onR. Indeed, for anyAĎ Ω, the supremum and infimum ofπ overAbelong toπpΩqby its compactness, whence π´1pinfxPAπpxqqconsists of the infima ofA, andπ´1psupxPAπpxqqconsists of its suprema.

Consider the p-boxpIr1s»,πq. Then, for anyAĎΩ, we deduce from Eq. (9) that EF,FpAq “FpsupAq “πpsupAq “sup

xPA

πpxq

becausexĺyfor allxPA if and only ifπpxq ďπpyqfor allxPA, by definition of ĺ, and hence, a minimal upper bound, or supremum,yforAmust be one for whichπpyq “ supxPAπpxq(and, again, suchyexists becauseπpΩqis compact).

The representing p-box is not necessarily unique:

Example 19. Let Ω“ tx1,x2u and let Π be the possibility measure determined by the possibility distribution

πpx1q “0.5 πpx2q “1.

As proven in Theorem 18, this possibility measure can be obtained if we consider the order x1ăx2and the p-boxpF1,F1qgiven by

F1px1q “0 F1px2q “1 F1px1q “0.5 F1px2q “1.

However, we also obtain it if we consider the orderx2ăx1and the p-boxpF2,F2qgiven by

F2px1q “1 F2px2q “0.5 F2px1q “1 F2px2q “1.

The p-boxpF2,F2qinduces a possibility measure from Corollary 13, also taking into ac- count thatΩis finite. Moreover, by Eq. (5),

EF

2,F2px2q “Fpx2q ´Fpx2´q “1 EF

2,F2px1q “Fpx1q ´Fpx1´q “0.5

as with the given ordering, x2´ “0´andx1´ “x2. As a consequence, EF

2,F2 is a possibility measure associated to the possibility distributionπ.

There are possibility measures which cannot be represented as p-boxes whenπpΩqis not compact:

Example 20. LetΩ“ r0,1s, and consider the possibility distribution given by πpxq “ p1`2xq{8 ifxă0.5,πp0.5q “0.4 andπpxq “xifxą0.5; note thatπpΩq “ r0.125,0.25q Y t0.4u Y p0.5,1sis not compact. The ordering induced byπis the usual ordering onr0,1s.

LetΠbe the possibility measure induced byπ. We show that there is no p-boxpF,Fqon pr0,1s,ĺq, regardless of the orderingĺonr0,1s, such thatEF,F“Π.

By Corollary 13, ifEF,F“Π, then at least one ofF orF is 0-1–valued. Assume first thatF is 0-1–valued. By Eq. (5),EF,Fptxuq “Fpxq ´Fpx´q “πpxq. Becauseπpxq ą0 for allx, it must be thatFpx´q “0 for allx, soF“π. BecauseFis non-decreasing,xĺy

(19)

if and only ifFpxq ďFpyq; in other words,ĺcan only be the usual ordering onr0,1sfor pF,Fqto be a p-box. Hence,F“It1u.

Now, withA“ r0,0.5q, we deduce from Proposition 7 that EF,FpAq “inf

AĺxFpxq “0.4ą0.25“sup

xPA

πpxq “ΠpAq,

where the second equality follows becauseBc“ t1u. Hence,EF,Fdoes not coincide with Π.

Similarly, ifF would be 0–1-valued, then we deduce from Eq. (5) thatFpxq “1 for everyx, again becauseπpxq ą0 for allx. Therefore, Fpx´q “1´πpxqfor allx. But, becauseF is non-decreasing,ĺcan only be the inverse of the usual ordering onr0,1sfor pF,Fqto be a p-box.

This deserves some explanation. We wish to show thatFpx´q ăFpy´qimpliesxăy.

Assume ex absurdo thatxąy. But, then, Fpx´q “sup

zăx

Fpzq ěsup

zăy

Fpzq “Fpy´q,

a contradiction. It also cannot hold thatx»y, because in that casezăxif and only if zăy, and whence it would have to hold thatFpx´q “Fpy´q. Concluding, it must hold thatxăywheneverFpx´q ăFpy´q, or in other words, wheneverxąy. So,ĺcan only be the inverse of the usual ordering onr0,1sand, in particular,r0,1s{ »is order complete.

Now, forpF,Fqto induce the possibility measureΠ, we know from Corollary 17 that Fpxq “Fpx`qfor everyxthat has no immediate successor in with respect toĺ, that is, for everyxă0, or equivalently, for everyxą0. Whence,

Fpxq “Fpx`q “inf

yąxFpyq “inf

yąxFpy´q “1´sup

yąx

πpyq “1´sup

yăx

πpyq

for allxą0. This leads to a contradiction: by the definition ofπ, we have on the one hand, Fp0.5´q “ sup

xă0.5

Fpxq “ sup

xą0.5

Fpxq “ sup

xą0.5

p1´sup

yăx

πpyqq “0.5 and on the other hand,

Fp0.5´q “1´πp0.5q “0.6.

Concluding,EF,Fcoincides withΠin neither case.

Another way of relating possibility measures and p-boxes goes via random sets (see for instance [19] and [9]). Possibility measures on ordered spaces can also be obtained via upper probabilities of random sets (see for instance [6, Sections 7.5–7.7] and [21]).

5.2. P-boxes as Conjunction of Possibility Measures. In [9], where p-boxes are studied on finite spaces, it is shown that a p-box can be interpreted as the conjunction of two possibility measures, in the sense thatMpPF,Fqis the intersection of two sets of additive probabilities induced by two possibility measures. The next proposition extends this result to arbitrary totally preordered spaces.

Proposition 21. LetpF,Fqbe a p-box such thatpF1“F,F1“IqandpF2“Ir1s»,F2“ Fqare possibility measures. Then,pF,Fqis the intersection of two possibility measures defined by the distributions

π1pxq “1´Fpx´q π2pxq “Fpxq in the sense thatMpPF,Fq “MpΠ1q XMpΠ2q.

Références

Documents relatifs

It is based on five 4-bit S-Boxes, a multiplexer (not shown), two finite field multiplications and two linear layers specified using binary matrices. These components are assembled in

His latest works are the co-authored Okinawa Under Occupation: McDonaldization and Resistance to Neoliberal Propaganda (Palgrave 2017) and the co-edited The

CMT Distal = Distal hereditary motor neuropathies (dHMN) = spinal CMT or distal spinal muscular atrophy (DSMA) See under MOTOR NEURONE DISEASES (Group 12) D. Other

an extension of the fiducial paradigm for statistical inference, while Shafer inter- preted these upper and lower probabilities as plausibility and belief functions with- out

In this chapter, we have tried to show that while probability theory properly cap- tures uncertainty due to the randomness of precisely observed phenomena, the rep- resentation

The paper is organised as follows: in Section 2, we give the basics of the behavioural theory of imprecise probabilities, and recall some facts about p-boxes and possibility

What these observations suggest is that what matters for the extension of the lived body/body schema in question is not the visual perception of a continuity and of a

Another phenomenon of more discreet endogenous evolution also seems to characterize the Amerindian occupation of the Lesser Antilles and Puerto Rico: the passage