• Aucun résultat trouvé

Topological aggregation, the twin paradox and the No Show paradox

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "Topological aggregation, the twin paradox and the No Show paradox"

Copied!
9
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-01356720

https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01356720

Submitted on 26 Aug 2016

HAL

is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers.

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire

HAL, est

destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés.

Topological aggregation, the twin paradox and the No Show paradox

Guillaume Chèze

To cite this version:

Guillaume Chèze. Topological aggregation, the twin paradox and the No Show paradox . Social

Choice and Welfare, Springer Verlag, 2017, �10.1007/s00355-017-1032-1�. �hal-01356720�

(2)

THE TWIN PARADOX AND THE NO SHOW PARADOX

GUILLAUME CH`EZE

Abstract. Consider the framework of topological aggregation introduced by Chichilnisky (1980). We prove that in this framework the Twin Paradox and the No Show Paradox cannot be avoided. Anonymity and unanimity are not needed to obtain these results.

Introduction

The goal of this note is to show that we cannot avoid some paradoxes in the topological social choice setting. Topological social choice has been introduced by Chichilnisky (1980). Nowadays, there exists different surveys and collections of papers about this topic, e.g. (Baigent 2011, Heal 1997, Lauwers 2000, 2009, Mehta 1997) and roughly speaking it is the study of continuous aggregation rules.

In the topological social choice framework, an aggregation rule betweenkagents is a function fromXktoX, whereX is a topological space. Chichilnisky has shown an impossibility result: there exists no continuous aggregation rule defined on the sphereSn satisfying anonymity and unanimity. This result has been proved inde- pendently by Eckmann (1954, 2004).

In this note we study the Twin Condition (roughly, identical twins have more power) and the Participation Condition (voting does not harm). With an homo- logical approach, we prove that on the sphereSn neither the Twin Condition nor the Participation Condition can be satisfied by a continuous aggregation rule. As the Twin Condition (respectively the Participation Condition) is not satisfied for continuous aggregation rule on the sphere we say that we have a Twin Paradox (respectively a No Show Paradox).

When we study the Twin Condition, two players have exactly the same prefer- ence. We can think about this situation in the following way: one player moves his/her preference to a new preferencex. Furthermore, this new preferencexwas already the preference of another player. Thusxis now the choice of more players.

Therefore, we hope that the new social preference will reflect this situation and will be closer tox.

There already exists papers studying the behavior of aggregation rules when players preferences move closer to the preference of another player.

Macintyre (1998) has used a convexity condition and a monotonicity condition in

Guillaume Ch`eze: Institut de Math´ematiques de Toulouse, Universit´e Paul Sabatier, 118 route de Narbonne, 31 062 TOULOUSE cedex 9, France

E-mail address:guillaume.cheze@math.univ-toulouse.fr.

Date: August 26, 2016.

1

(3)

2 G. CH `EZE

order to study this kind of situations for the circleS1. For two players with differ- ent preferences the convexity condition used by Macintyre is roughly the following:

the social outcome must be contained in the small semicircle with end-points the preference of these two players. The monotonicity condition means that if the first player moves his/her preference closer to the preference of the second player then the social outcome must not penalize the second player. With elementary methods and no algebraic topology Macintyre has shown that the only possible continuous aggregation rules with domainS1satisfying his convexity condition and the mono- tonicity condition are dictatorial. This result is given for two players with preference in S1. In the same article Macintyre has also studied the situation with k players with preferences in S1. In this case the convexity condition becomes: the social outcome must be contained in a semicircle containing a majority of players with end-points the preference of at least two of the players. Macintyre has then shown that there exists no continuous aggregation rule satisfying the convexity condition fork≥2 players. This result is still proved with elementary methods and only for the circleS1.

Duddy and Piggins (2012) have studied the role of what they called a proximity condition for merging function. A merging function is a functionf :Rk →R, where Rdenotes the real line. The role of a merging function is to aggregate real numbers x1, . . . , xk given by the players to a single value f(x1, . . . , xk). For example, the arithmetic mean is a merging function. The authors have studied merging function satisfying the following proximity condition: suppose thatevery xj moves strictly closer to some individual’s number xi then the merging function does not change or move closer to the individual’s number xi. In this context, closer means closer relatively to the usual distance on real numbers. Duddy and Piggins have shown that scale invariant functions satisfying their proximity condition are dictatorial.

Here we study functions with domain Sn, with n ≥ 1. Our Twin Condition is in the same vein than the conditions given by Macintyre, Duddy and Piggins.

However we prove that there exists no aggregation rule satisfying our condition.

Furthermore, contrarily to Macintyre, Duddy and Piggins we do not need to con- sider moves for every players or for a majority of voters, a condition about two players is sufficient to get our impossibility result.

In the discrete setting, the No Show Paradox has been introduced by Fishburn and Brams (1983). This paradox means that there exists a player who would rather not vote. Sometimes, this paradox is also called the Abstention Paradox.

Moulin (1988) has proved that if a voting function chooses the Condorcet winner when it exists, then this voting rule generates a No Show Paradox whenever there are at least 4 alternatives and 25 voters. We recall that outcomes of voting func- tions are singleton sets.

P´erez (2001) has studied a stronger version of the No Show paradox. This stronger version says that there exists a player whose favorite candidate loses the election if he/she votes honestly, but gets elected if he/she abstains. Perez has shown that almost all known voting rules suffer from this paradox.

Jimeno et al. (2009) has extended Moulin’s result to Condorcet voting correspon- dences. In this case, outcomes for the voting rule are nonempty sets and not singleton sets.

(4)

Recently, Brandt et al. (2016) has shown that Moulin’s result is still valid if there are at least 12 voters. Furthermore, this bound is optimal since the authors have given an example of a voting rule satisfying the Condorcet criterion and avoiding the No Show Paradox for up to 11 voters.

To the author’s knowledge, the No Show paradox has not been studied in the topological social choice framework. However, we can mention that there exists re- lations between the ”classical” social choice setting and the topological social choice setting. What we call ”classical” social choice is the study of aggregation rules in a discrete setting (with the discrete topology). The relation between this two setting has been given by Baryshnikov (1997). Baryshnikov and then Tanaka (2009) have given a proof of Arrow’s theorem using an homological strategy closed to the one given by Chichilnisky in her study of continuous aggregation rule over the sphere Sn. In this paper, we will also used an homological approach to prove our theorems.

The structure of this note is the following: In the first section we study the Twin Paradox, in the second section we study the No Show Paradox, and in an appendix we recall all the basic notions of algebraic topology used during our proofs.

1. The twin paradox In this section we define and study the Twin Paradox.

Suppose that an aggregation rule in a topological space X takes individual pref- erencesx1, . . . , xk and gives the social preference x. Then, suppose that the j-th player changes his point of view and decide to modify his choice from xj to xi. Then thei-th player and thej-th player have exactly the same preference and we can consider thej-th player as a twin of the i-th player. With this new situation, we can hope that the aggregation rule will give a new social preference closer toxi, if it is not the case we have a Twin paradox. Indeed,xi is now the choice of more players and then we hope that the new social preference will reflect this situation and will be closer to xi.

Here closer means that we considerxi in a metric space. We now define the Twin Condition which corresponds to the situation explained above.

Definition 1. Consider a metric space (X, d) wheredis the metric onX. We say thatf :Xk→X satisfies theTwin Conditionif for alli6=j and allx1, . . . , xk∈X withxi6=xj we have:

d

f(x1, . . . , xi, . . . , xj1, xi, xj+1, . . . , xk), xi

≤d

f(x1, . . . , xk), xi

,

and the inequality is strict forxi6=f(x1, . . . , xk).

The Twin Paradox is a situation where the Twin Condition is not satisfied.

In the following, we study the Twin Condition on the sphereSn. The distance between two points on the sphere is the length of a great circle joining these two points. Ifx, y∈Snthen we denote bydSn(x, y) the distance on the sphere between these two points. We havedSn(x, y) = arccos(x·y), wherex·y is the usual scalar product ofx, y∈Rn+1. We can already remark thatdSn(x, y)≤πfor allx, y∈Sn anddSn(x, y) =πmeansx=−y.

(5)

4 G. CH `EZE

The main result of this section is the following:

Theorem 2. For k≥3 players, there exists no continuous aggregation rule f : (Sn)k →Sn which satisfies the Twin Condition.

We remark that a dictatorship do not satisfy the Twin Condition, but the non- existence of an aggregation rule satisfying the Twin Condition is not straightfor- ward.

In order to prove this theorem we first prove that the Twin Condition on the sphere entails the following condition:

Definition 3. We say that f : Xk → X satisfies the Nowhere Anti-Unanimity Condition if for allx∈X we havef(x, x, . . . , x)6=−x.

Remark that this definition is still valid whenk= 1. This just means that the function satisfiesf(x)6=−x. Thus in the following we still use the term Nowhere Anti-Unanimity Condition even ifk= 1.

When the spaceX is the sphereSn with the distancedSn, we have:

Lemma 4. Suppose that f : (Sn)k → Sn satisfies the Twin condition then f satisfies the Nowhere Anti-Unaninimity Condition.

Proof. By contradiction. Assume the existence of a point x0 ∈ Sn such that f(x0, . . . , x0) = −x0. As f satisfies the Twin Condition we have for all y ∈ Sn such thaty6=x0:

π=dSn(−x0, x0) =dSn f(x0, . . . , x0), x0

≤dSn f(x0, . . . , x0, y, x0, . . . , x0), x0 . Then f(x0, . . . , x0, y, x0, . . . , x0

=−x0, thus x0 6=f(x0, . . . , x0, y, x0, . . . , x0 . In this situation the Twin Condition implies that the previous inequality is strict.

As the distance between two points on the sphere is never strictly bigger than than π, we get a contradiction and then we deduce that for all x ∈ Sn we have

f(x, . . . , x)6=−x.

Now, we introduce some notations.

Definition 5. We denote byδi,j(k) the following function:

δi,j(k):Sn −→ (Sn)k

x 7−→ (e1, . . . , e1, x, e1, . . . , e1, x, e1, . . . , e1)

where i 6=j, e1 = (1,0, . . . ,0) ∈Sn ⊂Rn+1 and x appears inδ(k)i,j(x) in the i-th andj-th coordinate.

Letf : (Sn)k→Sn be a function, we denote byfi,jthe function f◦δi,j(k).

With these notations we deduce the following lemma:

Lemma 6. If f : (Sn)k →Sn satisfies the Twin Condition then fi,j satisfies the Nowhere Anti-Unanimity Condition.

Proof. We consider the following functions f˜i,j : (Sn)2 → Sn

(x, y) 7→ f(e1, . . . , x, e1, . . . , e1, y, e1, . . . , e1)

(6)

where i 6=j, e1 = (1,0, . . . ,0) ∈Sn ⊂Rn+1 and x appears infi,j(x) in the i-th coordinate andy in the j-th coordinate.

Asf satisfies the Twin Condition then ˜fi,j satisfies also the Twin Condition. Thus by Lemma 4, ˜fi,j satisfies the Nowhere Anti-Unanimity Condition. Then for all

x∈Sn we havefi,j(x) = ˜fi,j(x, x)6=−x.

The following lemma will be used to show thatfi,j is homotopic to the identity function on the sphereidSn.

Lemma 7. If a continuous function g : Sn → Sn satisfies the Nowhere Anti- Unanimity Condition then g is homotopic toidSn.

Proof. We consider

h(t, x) = t.g(x) + (1−t).x kt.g(x) + (1−t).xk.

The functionhis well defined and continuous becausegsatisfies the Nowhere Anti- Unanimous Condition and then the denominator do not vanish. Furthermore, we haveh(0, x) =x=idSn(x) and h(1, x) =g(x). Then his an homotopy betweeng

andidSn.

The last ingredient for the proof of Theorem 2 is the following:

Lemma 8. Ifk≥3then there exists no continuous functionsf : (Sn)k→Snsuch that for all i6=j,fi,j is homotopic toidSn.

The proof of this lemma uses classical homological properties. All these proper- ties are recall in the appendix and are denoted by (P1), (P2), (P3) and (P4).

Proof. By contradiction. Suppose that there exists a continuous function f such thatfi,jis homotopic toidSn, for alli6=j. The singular homology gives a functor Hnwhich entails the following group homomorphism:

Hn(f) :Zk −→ Z (z1, . . . , zk) 7−→

k

X

α=1

dα×zα

wheredα∈Z.

Asfi,j =f ◦δi,j(k), by (P1) we have

Hn(fi,j) =Hn(f)◦Hni,j(k)).

By (P2) we deduce that

Hn(fi,j) :Z −→ Z

z 7−→ (di+dj)×z Thus

deg(fi,j) =di+dj,

where deg denotes the degree of a continuous function fromSn to Sn. Furthermore,fi,j is homotopic to idSnthen by (P3), and (P4) we have

deg(fi,j) = 1.

It follows

di+dj= 1 for alli6=j.

(7)

6 G. CH `EZE

Ask≥3 this gives: d1+d2=d1+d3=d2+d3= 1, and we deduced1= 1/2. As d1must be an integer we get a contradiction and this proves the desired result.

Now, we can prove Theorem 2.

Proof of Theorem 2. By contradiction. Suppose that there exists a continuous functionf satisfying the Twin Condition. By Lemma 6 and Lemma 7, for alli6=j we havefi,jhomotopic toidSn. Then Lemma 8 gives the desired contradiction.

2. The No Show Paradox

In this section we describe the No-Show Paradox in the topological social choice setting. In this situation we study the behavior of a family of aggregation rules.

Indeed, in this situation the number of agents will change. Thus we study a family of aggregation rules (f(k))kwhere the exponentkcorresponds to the number of agents.

We would like to have an aggregation rule for which each player has an incentive to give his preference. This means it is always better for players to give their preferences and to participate to the vote. This leads to the following definition:

Definition 9. Let (X, d) be a metric space and (f(k))k be a family of functions fromXk toX.

We say that the family of functions (f(k))k satisfies the Participation Condition if for allk≥2 and for allx1, . . . , xk+1 ∈X we have:

d

f(k+1)(x1, . . . , xi, . . . , xk+1), xi

≤d

f(k)(x1, . . . ,xˆi, . . . , xk+1), xi

,

and the inequality is strict forxi6=f(k)(x1, . . . ,ˆxi, . . . , xk+1).

The notation ˆxi means that we omitxi.

We remark that the Participation Condition implies

f(k+1)(x1, . . . , xi−1, f(k)(x1, . . . ,xˆi, . . . , xk+1), xi+1, . . . , xk+1) =f(k)(x1, . . . ,xˆi, . . . , xk+1).

This means that the Participation Condition entails that the vote of an outsider who agrees with the outcome will not change the outcome.

If a family of aggregation rule do not satisfies the Participation Condition then we say that we have a No Show Paradox.

In this section we prove that we cannot avoid the No Show Paradox:

Theorem 10. There exists no family fk(k) of continuous aggregation rules f(k): (Sn)k→Sn which satisfies the Participation Condition.

The proof of this theorem is similar to the one given for the Twin Paradox. We need to introduce the functionsfi,j(k)defined by fi,j(k)=f(k)◦δ(k)i,j.

Lemma 11. If the family of functionsf(k): (Sn)k →Sn satisfies the Participation Condition thenfi,j(k+1) satisfies the Nowhere Anti-Unanimity Condition.

Proof. By contradiction. If there existsx0∈Sn such thatfi,j(k+1)(x0) =−x0 then dSn fi,j(k+1)(x0), x0

=dSn(−x0, x0) =π

(8)

and the Participation Condition gives

dSn(fi,j(k+1)(x0), x0) = dSn f(k+1)(e1, . . . , e1, x0, e1, . . . , e1, x0, e1. . . , e1), x0

≤ dSn f(k)(e1, . . . , e1, x0, e1, . . . , e1), x0 . This impliesf(k)(e1, . . . , e1, x0, e1, . . . , e1) =−x0.

Thus x0 6= f(k)(e1, . . . , e1, x0, e1, . . . , e1) and in this situation the Participation Condition says that the previous inequality must be strict. Therefore,

π < dSn f(k)(e1, . . . , e1, x0, e1, . . . , e1), x0 .

This gives a contradiction and thus provesfi,j(k+1)(x)6=−x, for allx∈Sn. Proof of Theorem 10. By contradiction. Suppose that there exists a family of con- tinuous function satisfying the Participation Condition. By Lemma 11 and Lemma 7, for alli6=j we havef(k+1)homotopic toidSn. Then Lemma 8 gives the desired

contradiction.

Appendix: An algebraic topology toolkit

Our main tool is singular homology, see e.g. (Hatcher 2002, Rotman 1988). We recall briefly in this section some results from algebraic topology:

Singular homology gives a functorHnsuch that for a topological spaceX,Hn(X) is an abelian group. Classical examples are Hn(Sn) = Z and Hn (Sn)k

= Zk. Furthermore for a continuous function f :X →Y, the functor Hn gives a group homorphismHn(f) :Hn(X)→Hn(Y) and ifg:Y →Z is a continous function we have the following property:

(P1) : Hn(f ◦g) =Hn(f)◦Hn(g).

During our proofs we have used the continuous functionδ(k)i,j. The group homor- phismHni,j(k)) associated to this continuous function is

(P2) : Hni,j(k)) :Z −→ Zk

z 7−→ (0, . . . ,0, z,0, . . . ,0, z,0, . . . ,0) wherez appears inHn(k)i,j)(z) in thei-th andj-th coordinate.

Furthermore, if two continuous functionsf andg are homotopic then we have:

(P3) : Hn(f) =Hn(g).

A classical situation appears when we study a continuous functionf :Sn →Sn. We recall that in this situation Hn(f) is characterized by an integer called the degree of f and denoted by deg(f). The group homomorphismHn(f) :Z→Zis then given by z7→ deg(f)×z. The degree of the identity function on the sphere Sn is equal to 1. We have then the property:

(P4) : deg(idSn) = 1.

In this note, we consider continuous aggregation rules on the sphere Sn. If one single point is removed from the domain Sn, i.e. the domain of individual preferences is reduced toSn\ {x}with xin Sn, then our proof collapse. Indeed, we haveHn(Sn\ {x}) = 0.

(9)

8 G. CH `EZE

Acknowledgement

The author would like to thank the anonymous referees for their helpful com- ments. The expression “Nowhere Anti-Unanimity” is due to one of the referees.

References

Baigent, N.: 2011, Chapter Eighteen - Topological Theories of Social Choice, in K. J. Arrow, A. K. Sen and K. Suzumura (eds),Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, Vol. 2 ofHandbook of Social Choice and Welfare, Elsevier, chapter 18, pp. 301–334.

Baryshnikov, Y. M.: 1997, Topological and discrete social choice: in a search of a theory,Soc. Choice Welf.14(2), 199–209.

Brandt, F., Geist, C. and Peters, D.: 2016, Optimal bounds for the No-Show paradox via SAT solving. Proceedings of the 15th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems, AAMAS 2016.

Chichilnisky, G.: 1980, Social choice and the topology of spaces of preferences,Adv.

in Math.37(2), 165–176.

Duddy, C. and Piggins, A.: 2012, The proximity condition, Social Choice and Welfare39(2), 353–369.

Eckmann, B.: 1954, Rume mit mittelbildungen., Commentarii mathematici Hel- vetici28, 329–340.

Eckmann, B.: 2004, Social choice and topology a case of pure and applied mathe- matics,Expositiones Mathematicae 22(4), 385 – 393.

Fishburn, P. C. and Brams, S. J.: 1983, Paradoxes of Preferential Voting, Math.

Mag.56(4), 207–214.

Hatcher, A.: 2002,Algebraic topology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Heal, G. (ed.): 1997,Topological social choice, Springer, Berlin.

Jimeno, J. L., P´erez, J. and Garc´ıa, E.: 2009, An extension of the Moulin no show paradox for voting correspondences,Soc. Choice Welf.33(3), 343–359.

Lauwers, L.: 2000, Topological social choice,Mathematical Social Sciences40(1), 1 – 39.

Lauwers, L.: 2009, The topological approach to the aggregation of preferences,Soc.

Choice Welf. 33(3), 449–476.

Macintyre, I. D. A.: 1998, Two-person and majority continuous aggregation in 2-good space in social choice: A note,Theory and Decision 44(2), 199–209.

Mehta, P.: 1997, Topological methods in social choice: an overview,Soc. Choice Welf.14(2), 233–243.

Moulin, H.: 1988, Condorcet’s principle implies the no show paradox,J. Econom.

Theory 45(1), 53–64.

P´erez, J.: 2001, The strong no show paradoxes are a common flaw in Condorcet voting correspondences,Soc. Choice Welf.18(3), 601–616.

Rotman, J. J.: 1988, An introduction to algebraic topology, Vol. 119 of Graduate Texts in Mathematics, Springer-Verlag, New York.

Tanaka, Y.: 2009, On the equivalence of the Arrow impossibility theorem and the Brouwer fixed point theorem when individual preferences are weak orders, J.

Math. Econom.45(3-4), 241–249.

Références

Documents relatifs

Administration of high initial daclizumab doses (initial dose was 2 mg/kg) in concert with MMF and CsA trough lev- els between 120 and 130 ng/ml resulted in improved kid- ney

Actually we do not limit our study to masures associated to Kac-Moody groups: for us a masure is a set satisfying the axioms of [Héb17] (which are equivalent to the axioms of

Interestingly, while chronic oxidative stress increases tumor growth and spread, recent studies have demonstrated that high basal reactive oxygen species levels in breast and

GASTON SAINT-PIERRE 93 Résumons donc, pour conclure, que sur le plan linguistique l'étude d'une langue seconde pose des problèmes différents chez l'adulte que

We visited several manufacturing plants (truck manufacturing plant, medical instrument manufacturer, landing gear assembly plant, mold making and injection molding shops, etc.)

In a nutshell the general principles of a social democrat trade policy should be the followings: social protection and openness (especially to emerging countries products)

languages and practices of rights at least some of the tools they will need to make progress in dealing with the problems that Brown has identified.. I am not a lawyer, or even

The second semantics is a Kripke-style semantics, in which we require each agent’s set of doxastic alternatives to be equal to the set of worlds in which his explicit beliefs are