• Aucun résultat trouvé

Majority Stable Production Equilibria: A Multivariate Mean Shareholders Theorem

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "Majority Stable Production Equilibria: A Multivariate Mean Shareholders Theorem"

Copied!
39
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-01064883

https://hal-sciencespo.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01064883

Preprint submitted on 17 Sep 2014

HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires

Majority Stable Production Equilibria: A Multivariate Mean Shareholders Theorem

Hervé Crès

To cite this version:

Hervé Crès. Majority Stable Production Equilibria: A Multivariate Mean Shareholders Theorem.

2000. �hal-01064883�

(2)

M aj or it y St able P r oduct ion Equilibr ia:

A M ult ivar iat e M ean Shar eholder s T heor em ¤

Herv¶ e Crµ es

y

HEC School of Management

First version: March 2000 { This version: July 2000

A bst r act

In a simple paramet ric general equilibrium model wit h S st at es of nat ure and K · S

¯ rms | and t hus pot ent ially incomplet e market s| , rates of super majority rule ½2 [0; 1]

are comput ed which guarant ee t he exist ence of ½{ majority st able product ion equilibria:

wit hin each ¯ rm, no alt ernat ive product ion plan can rally a proport ion bigger t han ½of t he shareholders, or shares (depending on t he governance), against t he equilibrium. Under some assumpt ions of concavity on t he dist ribut ions of agent s' types, t he smallest ½are shown to obt ain for announced product ion plans whose span cont ains t he ideal securit ies of all K mean shareholders. These rat es of super majority are always smaller t han Caplin and Nalebu® (1988, 1991) bound of 1¡ 1=e ¼ 0:64. Moreover, simple majority product ion equilibria are shown t o exist for any init ial dist ribut ion of types when K = S ¡ 1, and for symmet ric dist ribut ions of types as soon as K ¸ S=2.

K eywor ds: Shareholders' vot e, general equilibrium, incomplet e market s, super majority.

JEL Classi¯ cat ion N umb er : D21, D52, D71, G39.

¤I am grat eful t o Alessandro Cit anna and Mich T vede for st imulat ing conversat ions and very helpful and const ruct ive comment s.

yHEC School of Management , 78351 Jouy-en-Josas, France; Tel: 33 1 39 67 94 12; cres@hec.fr; Fax:

33 1 39 67 70 85.

(3)

1 I nt r oduct ion

In t his paper, a simple paramet ric general equilibrium model wit h S st at es of nat ure and K · S ¯ rms | and t hus pot ent ially incomplet e market s| is st udied. T here is only one good, and t he agent s (consumers/ shareholders) are charact erized by ut ility funct ions exhibiting some quadrat ic feat ure and indexed by a probability vector ¼ in t he (S ¡ 1){

dimensional simplex, ¢

S

, t hat we call t he

type

of t he agent . Agent s' types are supposed t o be dist ribut ed, according a cont inuous measure wit h density f over ¢

S

, and are only endowed wit h init ial shares of t he K ¯ rms. Since t here is no consumpt ion in period zero,

¯ rms are t aken t o be asset s which allocat e a cert ain mass of t he good across st at es in period one.

Rat es of super majority rule ½ are comput ed which guarantee t he exist ence of ½{

majority stable product ion equilibria. The int erpret at ion follows. Given init ially an- nounced product ion plans, a general equilibrium is comput ed: agent s choose their opt imal port folio given t he market prices, and equilibrium prices for shares occur t hat clear t he market s. This product ion equilibrium is shown t o be ½{ majority st able in t he nat ural following sense: within each ¯ rm, t he product ion plans of ot her ¯ rms remaining ¯ xed, no alt ernat ive product ion plan can rally a proport ion bigger t han ½of t he shareholders, or shares, against the equilibrium.

T hese rat es of super majority rule are comput ed (1) under various governances, both of t he `one person-one vot e' and `one share-one vot e' types, and (2) when t he considered shares are t he init ial (pre-t rade) shares or t he equilibrium (post -t rade) shares. Condit ions are given under which t hese rates are smaller t han Caplin and Nalebu®(1988, 1991) bound of 64%. Moreover, it is shown that simple majority product ion equilibria exist for any initial dist ribut ion of types when K = S ¡ 1, and for symmet ric dist ribut ions of types as soon as K ¸ S=2. T hus, even wit h a high degree of market incomplet eness, a product ion equilibrium exist s against which, wit hin each ¯ rm, no alt ernat ive product ion plan can rally more t han half of t he shareholders, or shares.

T he early mot ivat ion of t his paper is t o st udy whet her collect ive choice mechanisms among t he society of shareholders | and in part icular t he simplest one: majority vot ing|

can help de¯ ning or qualifying t he object ive of t he ¯ rm in a cont ext of incomplet e market s.

T he lat t er concept has received a lot of int erest in t he recent years [see, e.g., Cit anna and Villanacci (1997), Dierker, Dierker and Grodal (1999) and Bet t zÄ uge and Hens (2000)].

In t he present set up, t he object ive of a ¯ rm is not invest igat ed from the perspect ive

of e± ciency or maximizat ion of some shareholder's value or pro¯ t funct ion [as in Drµ eze

(4)

(1974), Grossman and Hart (1979)], but from t he point of view of st ability wit h respect t o collect ive decision making among shareholders [as in Drµ eze (1987, 1989), DeMarzo (1993)], under di®erent types of governance.

T he result s proposed t end t o show t hat market equilibria exist which are stable with respect t o simple and quit e operat ional collect ive decision mechanisms (here: vot ing rules wit h reasonable rat es of super majority), even when t he degree of market incomplet eness can be considered `high'. Moreover t he less incomplet e t he market s t he smaller t he rat e of super majority necessary t o guarant ee t he exist ence of stable general equilibria. Al- t hough t hese int uit ive ¯ ndings are obtained in a simple set up, it is cert ainly valuable t o have posit ive result s of robust exist ence of majority majority st able product ion equilibria.

Especially given t he fact t hat t he Social Choice lit erat ure is perceived as being dominat ed by impossibility results and considered useless for a general t heory of decision in ¯ rms.

In st andard general equilibrium models of product ion in a cont ext of incomplet e mar- ket s [see, e.g., Magill and Quinzii (1996), Du± e and Shafer (1988) and Geanakoplos, Magill, Quinzii and Drµ eze (1990)], t he ¯ nancial st ruct ure is usually more complex than t he one present ed here. And t he di± culty in de¯ ning an object ive funct ion for a ¯ rm st ems from t he fact t hat, at equilibrium, shareholders can disagree on t he present value of t he product ion plans t hat are not in t he span of t he ¯ nancial st ruct ure: t o discount fut ure income st reams, t hey use shadow prices t hat can be di®erent . T hese shadow prices are endogeneous whereas in t he present paper, t hey are basically always point ing t oward t he ideal security which is exogeneously ¯ xed, by assumpt ion on t he ut ility funct ions.

T here is nevert heless a way t he present paper can shed some light on the debat e on which object ive funct ion t he ¯ rm should opt imize in the cont ext of incomplet e market s.

Firm should make choices t hat are support ed by shareholders, and t he most commonly suggest ed behavior for t he ¯ rm is t hat it should use t he average of t he shareholders' normalized present value vect or, where t he weights for averaging are t he shares of share- holders: a `mean' shareholder is t hus de¯ ned for each ¯ rm. If t he lat t er shares are t he

initial

shares, it is t he Grossman-Hart crit erion, if t hey are t he

equilibrium

shares, it is t he Drµ eze crit erion. The present paper gives some insight s that these two crit eria are likely t o give rise t o majority st able product ion equilibria (see Sect ion 4). The main result of t his paper is t hat

there exist production equilibria such that the

K

mean shareholders1 can exactly span their type and generate their ideal security (the one they would demand if markets were complete); moreover these are the most stable equilibria

. It is wort h not icing

1Of course, in Drµeze's case, as opposed t o Grossman-Hart 's, t he mean shareholder is endogeneously det ermined at equilibrium.

(5)

t hat t he assumpt ions under which t his result holds are weaker in t he case of a governance µ

a la Drµ eze.

T his result has no direct link wit h t he above-ment ioned crit eria since t he announced product ion plan of a ¯ rm does not have t o be t he opt imal product ion plan of it s mean shareholder. But t he collect ion of K product ion plans (called a mult iplan) should be such that t heir span cont ains t he ideal security of

all

mean shareholders; in some way t he mult iplan is opt imal for t he K mean shareholders. T hen t he product ion equilibria are st able for t he lowest possible rat es of super majority. Last ly, t he present paper does not st udy t he quest ion of optimality or const rained opt imality of t he st able equilibria it describes, a subject lying at the core of t he lit erat ure on product ion in a cont ext of incomplet e market s. Especially, it does not pursue t he study of Dierker, Dierker and Grodal (1999) on t he relat ion between majority vot ing and welfare considerat ions

2

.

Technically, t he main result s of t he present paper are based on t hose in Caplin and Nalebu® (1988, 1991). Indeed, the case where agent s are dist ribut ed over ¢

S

and t here is only one ¯ rm (K = 1, and t hen no exchange of shares), is a sub-case of Caplin and Nalebu® (1988, 1991). And of course we get here: ½= 1 ¡ 1=e ¼ 0:632. But alt hough some assumpt ions are less general t han t hose in Caplin and Nalebu® (1988, 1991), t he set up is di®erent , and more general in at least one dimension

3

. It is more general t o t he ext ent that t he number of asset s can be bigger t han one. It is di®erent t o t he ext ent t hat t here is an upst ream market mechanism, wit h equilibrium prices clearing market s for shares. Consequent ly t here is an endogeneous allocat ion of shares and t herefore an

endogeneous distribution over types

for governances µ a la Drµ eze. In t he present set up, t he collect ive choice mechanism is intertwined wit h a general equilibrium market mechanism.

T he paper is organized as follows. Sect ion 2 int roduces t he model and provides some preliminary result s founding t he analysis. Sect ion 3 focuses on t he canonical case where agents are described t hrough charact erist ics t hat are uniformly dist ribut ed over ¢

S

; exact comput at ions are provided illust rat ing how t he less incomplet e t he markets the smaller t he required rat es of super majority. Sect ion 4 discusses the generalizat ion of t he result s obt ained in t he previous sect ion: Caplin and Nalebu®(1988, 1991) general upper bound of 64% for t he rat e of super majority is shown t o hold in case t he dist ribut ions of charact er- ist ics ful¯ ll some condit ions of concavity (Proposit ion 3 and Theorem 3); simple majority

2Dierker, Dierker and Grodal (1999) show t hrough an example t hat majority vot ing and welfare considerat ions can be complet ely unrelat ed.

3Act ually, Caplin and Nalebu® (1991) gives, as an illust rat ion for a possible applicat ion of t heir t heory, t he example of vot ing among shareholders in a cont ext of incomplet e market s.

(6)

st able product ion equilibria are shown t o exist under some assumpt ions of symmet ry of t he dist ribut ions of charact erist ics (Proposition 2) or when t he degree of market incom- plet eness is just one (Theorem 2). Appendix A proposes some comment s; in part icular, t hrough paramet ric examples, t hese rat es are shown to decrease wit h t he homogeneity of t he shareholders' types, and t o increase wit h t he shareholders' pessimism. All t echnical proofs are gat hered in Appendix B and Appendix C.

2 T he model

Consider an economy wit h two periods, t = 0; 1 and S st at es of nat ure in period 1, indexed by s, s = 1; : : : ; S. T here is one good, and a cont inuum of agent s, each agent is indexed by probability vect or ¼= (¼

s

)

Ss= 1

which will be int erpret ed as his

ideal security

once t he ut ility functions ar int roduced. T he agent 's type ¼is t hus t aken in t he (S¡ 1)-dimensional simplex:

¢

S

=

(

¼= (¼

1

; ¼

2

; : : : ; ¼

S

) 2 R

S+

j

XS s= 1

¼

s

= 1

)

:

Agent s' types are assumed t o be dist ributed over ¢

S

according t o a cont inuous, at omless density function f : ¢

S

¡ ! R

+

. Consumpt ion t akes place in period one but must be decided in period zero. Agent ¼ is charact erized by a ut ility funct ion: U

¼

[x(¼)], where x(¼) = [x

1

(¼); : : : ; x

S

(¼)] is agent ¼'s consumpt ion in period 1. Since t here is only one good, it will be somet imes bet t er t o give a ¯ nancial int erpret at ion to x(¼) as an income vect or. Utility funct ions are of a quadrat ic/ `euclidean' type, described at t he end of t his sect ion.

T here are K ¯ rms indexed by k, k = 1; : : : ; K . All ¯ rms have t he same product ion t echnology, represent ed for t he simplicity of t he analysis by t he span of ¢

S

:

S

i =

(

y = (y

1

; y

2

; : : : ; y

S

) 2 R

S

j

XS s= 1

y

s

= 1

)

:

Agent ¼ is endowed wit h init ial shares of t he K ¯ rms: µ

0

(¼) = [µ

0k

(¼)]

Kk= 1

. He is t hen t ot ally charact erized by t he vect or [¼; µ

0

(¼)]. T he funct ion µ

0

: ¢

S

¡ ! R

K+

is t aken cont inuous and posit ive over ¢

S

.

A ¯ rm is basically an asset which allocat es an init ial mass ¡

0k

=

Z

¢S

f (¼) µ

k0

(¼) d¼ of the good across st at es in period 1. We do not normalize it t o one t o allow di®erent

¯ rms t o be of di®erent `sizes': t he yield, in t erms of consumpt ion/ income, of ¯ rm k in

period 1 in case st at e s occurs is: ¡

0k

y

ks

. To avoid some minor t echnical di± cult ies, it

(7)

is preferable not t o impose sign const raint s on product ion plans; t his is ¯ ne wit hin t he

¯ nancial int erpretat ion of t he model. Alt hough it is abusive t o t alk about ¯ rms in such a simple framework, and bet t er t o t alk about securit ies, we st ick to this t erminology and rely on t he forgiveness of t he reader.

M axim izat ion pr ogr am of t he agent s

Given an announced product ion plan y

k

by each ¯ rm (hence an announced mult i-plan Y = (y

k

)

Kk= 1

, where all y

k

's are t aken di®erent ) and a vect or of prices q = (q

k

)

Kk= 1

for t he shares, each agent maximizes his ut ility by choosing t he opt imal vect or of shares

4

µ(¼) = [µ

k

(¼)]

Kk= 1

and t he opt imal consumpt ion plan x(¼) according t o the maximizat ion program M (¼):

[µ(¼);x (¼)]

max U

¼

[x(¼)]

s. t .

XK k= 1

q

k

h

µ

k

(¼) ¡ µ

0k

(¼)

i

= 0 (1)

and x(¼) =

XK k= 1

µ

k

(¼) y

k

(2)

T his is of course equivalent t o ~ M (¼):

max

µ(¼)

U ~

¼;Y

[µ(¼)]

s. t .

XK k= 1

q

k

h

µ

k

(¼) ¡ µ

0k

(¼)

i

= 0 where ~ U

¼;Y

[µ(¼)] = U

¼

à K X

k= 1

µ

k

(¼) y

k

!

.

M aj or it y St able P r oduct ion Equilibr ium

Given t he individual demand funct ions for shares, an equilibrium price will clear t he market for shares.

D e¯ nit i on 1

A Production Equilibrium (PE) is a vector

E = (Y; q; µ(¼))

such that indi- vidual optimization

(C

1

)

, and market clearing

(C

2

)

, are satis¯ ed:

(C

1

)

Given

(Y; q)

, for all

¼

,

[µ(¼)]

solves the maximization program

M (¼) ~

;

(C

2

)

For all

k

,

Z

¢S

f (¼) µ

k

(¼) d¼=

Z

¢S

f (¼) µ

0k

(¼) d¼(= ¡

0k

)

.

4T he choice has been made here not t o impose short -sell const raint s on t he µ's. T he aim is t o prove exist ence of majority st able product ion equilibria, and t he paper is most ly going t o focus on equilibria such t hat µ(¼) > 0 for all ¼.

(8)

For a ¯ rm k, given a PE E, a dist ribut ion of vot ing weight s ´ : ¢

S

¡ ! R

K+

(´ ´ µ

0

or µ), and two product ion plans (y

k

; z

k

), denot e I

E;´

(y

k

) t he subset of agent s ¼ endowed wit h a positive vot ing weight

5

in ¯ rm k (i.e., agent s such t hat ´

k

(¼) ¸ 0), and denot e I

E;´

(z

k

; y

k

) [½ I

E;´

(y

k

)] t he subset of agent s ¼ endowed wit h a posit ive vot ing weight in

¯ rm k who prefer z

k

t o y

k

, i.e., such t hat

´

k

(¼) ¸ 0 and U

¼

[x(¼) + µ

k

(¼)(z

k

¡ y

k

)] ¸ U

¼

[x(¼)] ; where x(¼) is de¯ ned t hrough equat ions (2). De¯ ne:

P

E;´

(z

k

; y

k

) =

Z

IE ; ´(zk;yk)

f (¼) d¼

Z

IE ; ´(yk)

f (¼) d¼

and A

E;´

(z

k

; y

k

) =

Z

IE ;´(zk;yk)

f (¼) ´

k

(¼) d¼

Z

IE ; ´(yk)

f (¼) ´

k

(¼) d¼

;

respectively t he fract ion of shareholders (wit h vot ing right s) and t he fract ion of vot e shares who prefer z

k

t o y

k

. De¯ ne moreover

P

E;´

(y

k

) = sup

zk2 ¢S

P

E;´

(z

k

; y

k

) and A

E;´

(y

k

) = sup

zk2 ¢S

A

E;´

(z

k

; y

k

)

t he maximal fract ions (resp. of t he shareholders/ shares, wit h vot ing right s) against y

k

. D e¯ nit i on 2

For any real

½2 [0; 1]

, a

½

{ Majority Stable Production Equilibrium under

²

the `one person-one vote, pre-trade' governance (in short, a

½

{ MSPEp0) is a PE

E

such that for all

k

,

P

E;µ0

(y

k

) · ½;

²

the `one person-one vote, post-trade' governance (

½

{ MSPEp1) is a PE

E

such that for all

k

,

P

E;µ

(y

k

) · ½;

²

the `one share-one vote, pre-trade' governance (

½

{ MSPEa0), is a PE

E

such that for all

k

,

A

E;µ0

(y

k

) · ½;

²

the `one share-one vote, post-trade' governance (

½

{ MSPEa1), is a PE

E

such that for all

k

,

A

E;µ

(y

k

) · ½:

For

½= 1=2

, such an equilibrium is a simple{ Majority Stable Production Equilibrium (or s-MSPE).

5Only such agent s have t he right t o vot e in t he present set up.

(9)

R em ar k: T he p0 and p1-governance are not dist inct as soon as everybody is posit ively endowed wit h shares of all ¯ rms, bot h init ially and at equilibrium. This will be most ly t he case in t he present paper. It is clear t hat t he most interest ing governance is t he a1-governance. Nevert heless, t here is some di± culty in de¯ ning a ½{ Majority St able Pro- duct ion Equilibrium for t he a1-governance since t he number of post -t rade shares with vot ing rights,

Z

IY ; µ(yk)

f (¼) µ

k

(¼) d¼, is endogeneous and can be bigger t han t he init ial

allocat ion of shares, ¡

0k

, in case part of the agent s choose t o be short on k's st ock market

6

. But we will concent rat e in t his paper on product ion equilibria where all agent s are allo- cat ed posit ive post -trade shares. For ot her product ion equilibria, one can consider t hat t he excess number of shares is allocat ed in a cont inuous way (i.e., according t o f and µ

0

) t o all ot her shareholders, which does not int roduce much dist orsion in t he model.

T he concept of ½{ majority st able equilibrium (for K = 1) is linked t o t he Simpson- K ramer min-max majority [see Simpson (1969), K ramer (1977)]. In t he present paper t he concept is built t o hold for K ¸ 1: min-max majorit ies for product ion equilibria are (resp., for each governance):

½

¤p0

= inf

P E (Y;q;µ)

max

k

P

Y;µ0

(y

k

) , ½

¤p1

= inf

P E (Y;q;µ)

max

k

P

Y;µ

(y

k

)

½

¤a0

= inf

P E (Y;q;µ)

max

k

P

Y;µ0

(y

k

) and ½

¤a1

= inf

P E (Y;q;µ)

max

k

P

Y;µ

(y

k

) :

A ssum pt ions on t he ut ilit y funct ions U

¼

T he ut ility funct ions U

¼

are de¯ ned on R

S

and assumed t o sat isfy t he two following set s of assumpt ions:

² Assumpt ion (A) : U

¼

is increasing, st rict ly quasi concave, continuously di®erent iable and homot het ic;

² Assumpt ion (E) : The indi®erences surfaces of U

¼

cut h¢

S

i t hrough hyperspheres cent ered on ¼.

Taking homot het ic ut ility funct ions will allow t o focus on consumpt ions in h¢

S

i (since we'll only consider PE wit h

7

q = 1

K

, see next subsection). Assumpt ion (E) (said t o be t he `euclidean' assumpt ion) is more problemat ic: it is st andard in Social Choice t heory,

6In fact , t he st ock repurchase plans t hat some ¯ rms implement might be considered as int roducing some type of endogeneity in t he t ot al numbers of shares.

7Not at ion: q = 1K st ands for qk = 1; all k.

(10)

and t aken for purely t echnical reasons. T he mot ivat ion behind t his assumpt ion is t he following: when asked whet her t hey agree wit h an in¯ nit esimal change

8

u 2 R

S

in t he product ion plan of ¯ rm k, indi®erent shareholders should be on a

hyperplane

in ¢

S

. It is nevert heless clear that such ut ility funct ions exhibit some form of quadrat ic feat ure, an such feat ures are regularly assumed in t he ¯ nance lit erat ure, e.g., in t he CAPM.

When t here is only one ¯ rm (K = 1) as in Caplin and Nalebu® (1988, 1991), it is enough t o t ake ut ility funct ions of t he separable form:

U

¼

[x(¼)] =

XS s= 1

¼

s

v

s

[x

s

(¼)] : (3)

In t hat case, the type ¼ is t he subject ive probability of t he agent over st at es of nat ure.

T he fact that t he element ary ut ility funct ions are common across t he populat ion secures t he needed condit ion [see Grandmont (1978)]. The reason is simple t o see: when K = 1, x(¼) = y

1

is independent of ¼; and for any in¯ nit esimal change u 2 R

S

in t he produc- t ion plan, shareholders indi®erent t o t he proposed change are described by t he equat ion

P

s

¼

s

u

s

D v

s

[y

1

] = 0 which de¯ nes a hyperplane. If K > 1, shareholders indi®erent t o an in¯ nit esimal change u in the product ion plan of ¯ rm k are described by t he equat ion

P

s

¼

s

u

s

D v

s

[¹x

s

(¼)] = 0, where ¹x

s

(¼) st ands for t he opt imal consumpt ion of agent ¼, and di®ers across ¼. For inst ance, in t he log-linear case where v

s

´ ln, t he lat t er equat ion almost never de¯ nes a hyperplane in ¢

S

. But some of t he result s proposed in t he paper are valid wit h ut ility funct ions of t he form (3); t his discussion is posponed t o Sect ion 4.4.

A last di± culty is t o avoid negat ive consumpt ions/ incomes. We basically discard t his problem: (

i

) in case t he ut ility funct ions are of the separable form (3), by assuming t hat v

s

sat is¯ es t he Inada condit ions: lim

x¡ ! 0

D v

s

(x) = + 1 ; (

ii

) in case t he ut ility funct ions sat isfy assumpt ion (E), by endowing t he agents wit h an appropriat e quant ity, x

0

(¼), of t he consumpt ion good, what ever t he occuring st at e of nat ure

9

.

T he Par et o cr it er ion

Among all product ion equilibria, we will rest rict our at t ent ion t o t hose t hat respect t he Paret o criterion: an eligible product ion plan for majority st ability should be such t hat

8As already writ t en in t he int roduct ion, t he assumpt ion of concavity of t he individual ut ility funct ions ent ails t hat t he most challenging product ion plans are in¯ nit esimally close t o t he st aus quo; see Lemma 2 in Appendix B. T herefore, a challenger is basically an in¯ nit esimal change u in t he product ion plan, wit h, given t he t echnological const raint s,P

sus= 0.

9Since we will only consider mult iplans Y which spans a hyperplane having a non-empty int ersect ion wit h ¢S, a uniform upper bound can be found on x0(¼), for all ¼.

(11)

t here does not exist an alt ernat ive product ion plan preferred by

all

shareholder endowed wit h a vot ing right (i.e., endowed with a posit ive quantity of shares). T he following observat ion shows t hat , in t he present framework, a necessary and su± cient condit ion is t hat st ock prices be all equal

10

.

Obser vat ion 1

A PE

(Y; q; µ)

satis¯ es the Pareto criterion if and only if

q = 1

K. Proof

: Consider a PE (Y; q; µ) such t hat q 6 = 1

K

. Consider two ¯ rms, k and j , such t hat q

k

> q

j

; t hen t here exist s an alternat ive anounced product ion plan z

k

unanimously prefered t o y

k

by agent s posit ively endowed wit h shares of ¯ rm k. Suppose, wit hout loss of generality, t hat q

1

> q

2

. At t he PE (Y; q; µ), t he gradient of U

¼

[x(¼)] wit h respect t o µ(¼) is colinear t o q. Given q

1

> q

2

, this ent ails that for all ¼: D U

¼

[x(¼)] ¢(y

1

¡ y

2

) > 0.

Consider z

1

= y

1

+ ²(y

1

¡ y

2

), we t hen have, for ² small enough and for all ¼, U

¼

[x(¼) + µ

1

(¼)(z

1

¡ y

1

)] > U

¼

[x(¼)] if µ

1

(¼) > 0. Hence for t he `if' part of t he assert ion. The `only if' part is obviously t rue. 2

In t he sequel of t he paper, we'll de¯ ne a Paret o product ion equilibrium as a PE wit h unit prices: (Y; 1

K

; µ).

Denot e hY i t he vect orial subspace, in h¢

S

i , spanned by Y . At a PE wit h unit prices, t he opt imal choice of an agent is | up t o mult iplicat ion by a scalar, given assumpt ion (A)| the

point of tangency

between hY i and t he sect ions by h¢

S

i of t he agent 's indi®er- ence curves. This optimal point is t he

orthogonal projection

of ¼on hY i when assumpt ion (E) is ful¯ lled.

T his last property ent ails t he following geomet ric int erpret at ion, µ a la Caplin and Nale- bu®, of t he main argument of t he paper (proven in Lemma 2 in Appendix B): trying t o

¯ nd a best challenger t o y

k

, wit hin t he product ion plans of ¯ rm k (t he product ion plans of ot her ¯ rms remaining ¯ xed), reduces t o t ry and cut t he support , ¢

S

, of t he agent s' types by an hyperplane

containing

hY i in such a way as t o maximize t he di®erence in volume of t he two result ing pieces | a volume comput ed using t he dist ribut ion of vot ing weight s, as t he governance speci¯ es it.

10DeMarzo (1993) proves t hat a product ion plan which is st able wit h respect t o a `unanimity responsive' collect ive decision rule should be chosen by using a normalized present value vect or in t he convex hull of t hose of all shareholders. A `unanimity responsive' collect ive decision rule is such t hat it should be able t o implement an alt ernat ive product ion plan t hat Paret o dominat es t he incumbent . See also Proposit ion 31.3 in Magill and Quinzii (1996).

(12)

A fundam ent al pr elim inar y r esult

It st at es t hat any vect orial subspace in h¢

S

i can be spanned by a mult iplan Y that can be associat ed wit h a PE wit h equal unit prices.

L em m a 1

Under assumption (A), any multiplan

Y = (y

k

)

Kk= 1 generates a vector ial sub- space that can be supported by a production multiplan associated to a PE with unit prices:

there exists a production multiplan

Y = ( ~ ~ y

k

)

Kk= 1, with

y ~

1

= y

1, such that

hY i ´ h~ Y i

, and

( ~ Y ; 1

K

; ~ µ)

is a PE. Moreover,

y

1 can be chosen such that

µ(¼) > 0 ~

for all

¼

.

Proof

: See Appendix A. 2

T his fundament al Lemma allows t o focus only on t he span hY i of a mult iplan Y , and not on t he mult iplan it self. Moreover, t he fact that ~ µ(¼) can be t aken st rict ly posit ive for all ¼ secures t hat all shareholders have t he right t o vot e and t hat t he considered dist ribut ions of vot ing weight s are positive over t he whole support ¢

S

.

3 T he canonical case

We consider t he canonical case of uniform dist ributions of init ial characterist ics in t he set of types ¢

S

. Assumpt ions:

² for t he p0-governance: t he distribut ion f is uniform and µ

0k

(¼) > 0 for all k, all ¼;

² for t he p1-governance: t he distribut ion f is uniform and

Pk

µ

k0

(¼) > 0 for all ¼;

² for t he a0-governance: t he dist ribut ion f ¢µ

k0

is uniform for all k;

² for t he a1-governance: t he dist ribut ion f ¢

P k

µ

0k

is uniform.

It is wort h not icing t hat t he result s of t he present sect ion remain valid under t he assump-

t ion of separable ut ility funct ions of t he type (3) (see Claim 2 in Sect ion 4.4) and t hat

t he preceding set of assumpt ions are weaker for governances µ a la Drµ eze, i.e., based on

post -t rade shares, t han for governances µ a la Grossman-Hart .

(13)

3.1 Exist ence of M SP E

For any ¯ xed posit ive int egers S and K , K · S, de¯ ne

11

½

S;K

= 1 ¡

0

@ j S¡ 1

K

k j S¡ 1

K

k

+ 1

1 A

b

S ¡ 1K

c

: (4)

T heor em 1

Fix

K

and

S

. T here always exist, in the canonical case,

½

S;K{ MSPE12 for all governances of De¯ nition 2. Hence

½

¤

· ½

S;K for all four governances.

When K = 1, t here are no t ransact ion between agents and everybody keeps it s init ial share of t he ¯ rm; since t he shares are uniformly dist ribut ed accross agent s, t hen t he four governances coincide, and t he above result is a part icular case of Caplin and Nalebu®

(1988), which gives as a uniform upper bound: 1 ¡ 1=e ¼ 0:632. This upper bound is approached for t he present concept of majority vot ing equilibrium in t he case where t he number of asset s (or ¯ rms) is negligible wit h respect t o t he number of st ates of t he world.

In ot her cases t he rat e of super-majority rule t hat guarant ees t he exist ence of a MSPE is lower t han t his previous bound. For example, what ever t he number of st at es of nat ure, if S=3 · K < S=2 [resp. S=4 · K < S=3] t hen a rat e of 56% [resp. 60%] su± ces. Anot her example is t he following immediat e corollary.

Cor ollar y 1

S{ MSPE exist as soon as

K ¸ S=2

for all four governances.

T hus, even wit h a high degree of market incomplet eness, a product ion equilibrium exists against which, wit hin each ¯ rm, no alt ernat ive product ion plan can rally more than half of t he shareholders, or shares. T he sequel of this sect ion is a proof of Theorem 1 which goes t hrough t he design of t he `right ' securit ies.

3.2 B asic const r uct i on of a M SP E

T he aim is t o const ruct a ½{ MSPE for t he lowest possible ½. For ¯ xed S and K , de¯ ne n =

¹

S ¡ 1 K

º

, so t hat S = nK + m, wit h 1 < m · K . We t hen const ruct t he following part it ion of t he set of st at es of nat ure int o K subset s (according t o t he nat ural order, t he m ¯ rst subset s cont ain n + 1 element s, t he K ¡ m ot hers cont ain only n element s):

S

k

= f (k ¡ 1)(n + 1) + 1; : : : ; k(n + 1)g for 1 · k · m T

k

= f m + (k ¡ 1)n + 1; : : : ; m + kng for m + 1 · k · K

11For any real x, we denot e by bxc t he largest int eger smaller or equal t o x, and by dxe t he smallest int eger larger or equal t o x.

12In fact t here is a cont inuum of such MSPE (see t he proof ).

(14)

De¯ ne t he K product ion plans ¹ Y = ( ¹y

k

)

Kk= 1

, such t hat : for k · m; ¹y

ks

=

8<

:

1

n+ 1

if s 2 S

k

0 ot herwise ; for k ¸ m + 1; ¹y

sk

=

8<

:

1

n

if s 2 T

k

0 ot herwise (5) T he main argument revolves around t he following proposit ion which is a more developed rest at ement of Theorem 1.

P r op osit ion 1

Fix

S

and

K

. T hanks to Lemma 1, there exist PE

( ~ Y ; 1

K

; ~ µ)

that are

½

S;K{ MSPE for the four governances. They are such that

h~ Y i ´ h¹ Y i

and for all

¼

, the optimal consumption is

~

x(¼) =

X

k

µ ~

k

(¼) ~ y

k

=

X

k

¹µ

k

(¼) ¹y

k

where

¹µ

is de¯ ned by13:

¹µ

k

(¼) =

8>

>>

<

>>

>:

¼

Sk if

k · m

¼

Tk if

k ¸ m + 1

: (6)

Proof

: See Appendix B. 2

Exam ple: When bot h f and µ

0

are t aken uniform (and normalized), and all ¯ rms have t he same size (¡

0k

is independent of K ), an example of such a PE ( ~ Y ; 1

K

; ~ µ) is:

for k · m; ~ y

k

= (n + 1)K

S ¹y

k

¡ 1 S

XK j = m+ 1

¹y

j

; and for k ¸ m + 1; ~ y

k

= ¹y

k

; (7)

and µ ~

k

(¼) =

8>

>>

<

>>

>:

S

(n+ 1)K

¼

Sk

if k · m

¼

Tk

+

(n+ 1)K1

¼

S

if k ¸ m + 1 :

A geomet ric int erpret at ion of Proposit ion 1 will be helpful t o underst and t he proof and t he basic int uit ion of t he const ruct ion. As writ t en before, given t hat market equilibrium prices are 1

K

, t he opt imal choice of an agent is t he point of t angency between hY i and t he sect ions by h¢

S

i of t he agent 's indi®erence curves. Denot e ~ § (¼) t he section by h¢

S

i of t he indi®erence curve going t hrough t he opt imal choice ~ x(¼) (cf. Figure 1.a below).

A change in t he product ion plan ~ y

k

(or equivalent ly ¹y

k

) of ¯ rm k will t hen move h¹ Y i in

13Denot e, for a subset V of t he set of st at es of nat ure, ¼V = X

s2 V

¼s.

(15)

such a way t hat it st ill goes t hrough all ot her ~ y

j

's. This change, ¯ xing the shares at t heir post -t rade values, project s t he equilibrium consumpt ion ~ x(¼) inward or outward ~ § (¼), hence result ing in an improving or impairing change of t he ut ility level of agent ¼ (cf.

Figure 1.b below).

Lemma 2 in Appendix B shows t hat ¯ nding a best challenger t o ~ y

k

, wit hin t he pro- duct ion plans of ¯ rm k (t he product ion plans of ot her ¯ rms remaining ¯ xed), amount s t o ¯ nding t he

in¯ nitesimal move

of ~ y

k

which improves t he welfare of the biggest propor- t ion of shareholders or shares. Given assumpt ion (E), t his reduces t o t ry and cut ¢

S

by a hyperplane (orthogonal t o t his in¯ nit esimal change) cont aining hY i in such a way as t o maximize t he di®erence in volume of t he two result ing pieces. The best in¯ nit esimal change (of ~ y

k

) is point ing t oward t he largest piece. As in Caplin and Nalebu® (1988) it is shown t hat , when t he dist ribut ion of init ial charact erist ics is uniform, t he most chal- lenging in¯ nit esimal change of t he product ion plan ~ y

k

is t o sacri¯ ce one st at e of nat ure t o t he bene¯ t of all ot hers

14

, and implement a change

³

¡ ²;

S¡ 1²

; : : : ;

S¡ 1²

´

.

3.3 G eom et r i c i ll ust r at i on: S = 3 and K = 2

In t he case S = 3 and K = 2, and under t he assumpt ions given in t he example following Proposit ion 1, wit h ¹y1= (1=2; 1=2; 0) and ¹y2= (0; 0; 1), and t herefore ~y2= ¹y2 and ~y1= (2=3; 2=3; ¡ 1=3), one get s:

[~µ1(¼); ~µ2(¼)] = µ3

4[¼1+ ¼2]; ¼3+ 1

4[¼1+ ¼2]

and [¹µ1(¼); ¹µ2(¼)] = ¡

1+ ¼2]; ¼3¢ : T his is drawn on Figure 1.a; t he indi®erence curve ~§ (¼) corresponding t o t he opt imal ut ility level for agent ¼ is drawn: it is a circle around t he ideal security ¼. An illust rat ion of t he previous discussion is now provided in t his simple case and basically holds for t he four governances.

Opt i m al cut t ing of t he si m pl ex : It should be clear on t he drawing why ( ~Y ; 12; ~µ) is majority st able for t he simple-majority rule under all four governances. Indeed, consider, inst ead of ~y2, anot her proposal

~

y02 (see Figure 1.b). T he shares being ¯ xed, t he new consumpt ion of agent ¼ will become ~x(¼)0which dives inward ~§ , hence result ing in a higher ut ility. But for t he symmet ric (wit h respect t o h¹Y i ) agent , charact erized by type ¼¿ = (¼2; ¼1; ¼3), who at equilibrium consumes t he same ~x(¼¿) = ~x(¼), t his is an impairing change. Hence at least half of t he agent s (t he left part of t he t riangle) ¯ nds it impairing t hat any rightward change of t he product ion plan of ~y2 be implement ed. Symmet rically, any, even in¯ nit esimal, leftward change of ~y2 is going t o be blocked by t he agent s on t he right -hand side of h¹Y i . Finally, since bot h agent s ¼ and ¼¿ have t he same share of ¯ rm 2, it is obviously t he case t hat t he simple-majority st ability property holds for t he four types of governance. T he same type of argument holds t o prove

14T his is act ually very classical in Social Choice t heory and illust rat ed by t he problem of having t o divide a pie among S individuals; what ever t he init ial allocat ion, t here is a majority of S¡ 1S t o expropriat e one individual of his share and dist ribut e it evenly t o t he ot hers.

(16)

Figure 1.a Figure 1.b

(1; 0; 0) (0; 1; 0)

~

y2= ¹y2= (0; 0; 1)

¹y1

²

²

~ y1

²

²

² ¼

~ x(¼)

§~

²

²

²

²

²

~ y2

~ y20

~ x ~x0

¼

²

¼¿

~ y1 ²

©©*

¾

t hat any change in t he product ion plan ~y1 is going t o be blocked by at least half of t he shareholders, in number and volume of shares.

Moreover it is clear t hat t here are many ways t o cut ¢3int o two pieces of equal sizes. T he two pieces do not have t o be symmet ric. Act ually, Lemma 1 shows t hat any cut t ing of ¢3can be spanned by two product ion plans (y1; y2) which will generat e a PE wit h unit prices, hence securing t hat t he fundament al geomet rical int erpret at ion of T heorem 1 be valid. T his ensures a cont inuum of s-MSPE is t he present simple case.

Figure 1.c Figure 1.d

^ y1

²

²

²

²

² ¼

~ x

^ y01

^ y2

~ x0

a b

²

²

²

¼¿

¹§

¹y2

²

²

²

²

¹x(¼)

¼

¹y1 ±¹y1

±¹x(¼)

~ y1 ²

¡ ¡µ

¡¡µ

?

?

M ult i pl ici t y of t he M SP E: T here are a cont imuun of PE t hat end up wit h t he same \ cut t ing" of ¢S

(17)

wit h unit prices q = 12for bot h asset s, and unchanged ¹µ (see Lemma 1): for all ®, y1= (13+ ®;13+ ®;13¡ 2®) and y2 = (13¡ ®;13 ¡ ®;13+ 2®) will always found a PE wit h q = 12 and equilibrium shares ¹µ. (Not ice

~

® = 13.) For example, wit h ^® = 16, one get s ^y1 = ¹y1 = (1=2; 1=2; 0) and ^y2 = (1=6; 1=6; 2=3), wit h:

[^µ1(¼); ^µ2(¼)] = ¡

1+ ¼2] ¡ 12¼3;32¼3¢

so t hat ^x(¼) = ~x(¼) = ¹x(¼) (see Figure 1.c). T he drawn change from ^y1 t o ^y10will be ut ility improving for agent ¼, but ut ility impairing for agent ¼¿. Not ice here t hat all agent s charact erized by a type ¼such t hat ¼3¸ 2=3 (i.e., above t he dot t ed line [a; b]), do not have the right to vote under governances based on post -t rade shares since t heir post -t rade shares in ^y1are negat ive.

Hence t he same rule as before is ful¯ lled: any rightward (resp. leftward) change in t he product ion plan

^

y1will be blocked by (at least ) t he left -hand (resp. right -hand) side of t he t riangle, whose t op has been cut -o®. It is t o avoid t he minor and irrelevant t echnical di± culty of having t o comput e relat ive volumes in a cut -o® simplex t hat PE are cont ruct ed for which all shares allocat ed at equilibrium are posit ive (i.e., wit h ® > 1=3).

A sset s w it h di®er ent pr ices, t he Par et o cr it er i on: One can easily see t hat any proposed change of ~y1 along t he line h¹Y i will be unanimously reject ed. T his fact is linked t o t he reason why t here is no majority st able product ion equilibrium wit h announced product ion plans ( ¹y1; ¹y2): in fact t he PE based on t his mult iplan does not sat isfy t he Paret o crit erion (see Observat ion 1). Indeed, t he equilibrium price vect or is t hen such t hat q1> q2: t he shareholders will ¯ nd it opt imal t o `load' more t han in t he above case t heir port folio wit h shares of ¹y2 (see Figure 1.d) t o reach t he opt imal consumpt ion ¹x(¼). As drawn on Figure 1.d, t he opt imal ut ility level will t hen generat e an indi®erence surface ¹§ not t angent t o h¹Y i . Given t he quasi-concavity of t he ut ility funct ions, any change ±¹y1 of ¹y1 t oward ~y1 will be unanimously support ed, since t he consecut ive change ±¹x(¼) is always ut ility improving. T his is t rue unt ill ¹y1reaches

~ y1.

4 M or e gener al cases

In t his sect ion, more general density funct ions, f , and init ial dist ribut ions of shares, µ

0

, are invest igat ed. To avoid minor t echnical di± cult ies that would make t he reading less confort able wit hout making t he problem richer, we consider only st rict ly posit ive initial dist ribut ions of charact erist ics: µ

0

(¼) > 0 and f (¼) > 0 for all ¼. The aim is t o generalize as much as possible t he result s of t he previous sect ion. In a ¯ rst subsect ion, we invest igat e, for unspeci¯ ed f and µ

0

, t he case of complete market s, along wit h t he case of incomplete market s wit h only one dimension of incomplet eness. T hen we consider t he case of

symmetric

dist ribut ions of charact erist ics (subsect ion 4.2). For t hese two cases,

simple

majority product ion equilibria are shown t o exist . Finally, t he case of º -concave dist ribut ions of charact erist ics is considered (subsect ion 4.3), an assumpt ion regarded as imposing some measure of consensus in t he society of shareholders. Caplin and Nalebu®

(1991) result s are t hen used t o provide rat ios of ½-majority st able product ion equilibria.

(18)

4.1 T he cases K = S, K = S ¡ 1

T he case K = S is t rivial, since for a PE (Y; 1

K

; µ) | whose exist ence is secured by Lemma 1| every agent of type ¼ is able t o generat e it s idiosyncrat ic ideal security:

[

P k

µ

0k

(¼)] ¢¼. In t his case, in equilibrium, all y

k

's are

unanimously

support ed against any alt ernat ive product ion plan for any f and any init ial dist ribut ion of shares µ

0

; i.e., P

Y;µ0

(y

k

) = A

Y;µ0

(y

k

) = P

Y;µ

(y

k

) = A

Y;µ

(y

k

) = 0 for all k, as t he t heory of complet e market s predict s. We t hus have t he following observat ion.

Obser vat ion 2

I f

K = S

, for any density

f

and any initial distributions of shares

µ

0, there exist PE which are stable for any voting rule (even infra-majority voting rule15).

T he case K = S ¡ 1 is more di± cult and int erest ing. As far as the p0 and p1- governances are concerned, t he argument is st raighforward since t he same dist ribut ion of vot ing weight s, f , is t aken for all ¯ rms. Therefore a median-vot er-like argument allows t o go t hrough: For a PE (Y; 1

K

; µ), we know t hat ¯ nding a best challenger t o t he announced product ion plan y

k

amount s t o cut t he support of agent s' types by a hyperplane cont aining hY i . But t here is a unique such hyperplane, i.e., hY i it self. Therefore, t o prove exist ence of a s{ MSPE, it is enough to choose hY i such t hat it separat es ¢

S

int o two pieces of equal measure wit h respect t o f . T his is obviously always possible, and t here is an in¯ nit e number of ways t o do so as soon as S > 2. T hanks t o Lemma 1, we know t hat such a hyperplane can be supported by a PE wit h unit prices and posit ive shares.

T he argument is more complicat ed for governances based on shares, e.g., t he a0 and a1-governances. Indeed, hY i should be chosen such t hat it separat es ¢

S

int o two pieces of equal measure

simultaneously

wit h respect t o K (= S ¡ 1) dist ribut ions of vot ing weight s.

Hence a `mult ivariat e-median-vot er' argument is necessary. The following proposition, based on degree t heory and using t he Borsuk-Ulam t heorem, is shown.

16

T heor em 2

I f

K = S ¡ 1

, there exist s-MSPE for any

f

and any

µ

0, for all four gover- nances.

Proof

: To prove exist ence of s{ MSPEa0 one has t o choose hY i t hat separates ¢

S

int o two pieces of equal measure wit h respect t o t he dist ribut ions f ¢µ

0k

, for all k.

15An infra-majority vot ing rule is a majority rule wit h rat e ½< 1=2, i.e. such t hat an alt ernat ive a defeat s an alt ernat ive b if a proport ion bigger t han ½of t he populat ion prefers a t o b; hence it is possible t hat two alt ernat ives defeat each ot her at t he same t ime.

16It is wort h not icing t hat it remains valid under assumpt ion (A) only (cf. Claim 1 in Sect ion 4.4) on t he ut ility funct ions for t he governance based on pre-t rade shares.

(19)

Consider t he (S ¡ 2){ unit sphere (of dimension S ¡ 2) S

S¡ 2

. For any point Á on t he sphere, denote hÁi t he hyperplane (of dimension S ¡ 2) in h¢

S

i t hat is ort hogonal to t he vect or

¡ !

0Á and divides ¢

S

int o two pieces of equal measure wit h respect t o t he dist ribut ion f ¢

P k

µ

k0

. Denot e hÁi

+

t he one of t hese two pieces t oward which

¡ !

0Á points. For any k, 1 · k · K ¡ 1 (= S ¡ 2), denot e ¹

0k

(Á) t he (cont inuous) measure of hÁi

+

wit h respect t o t he dist ribut ion f ¢µ

k0

. A generalizat ion of t he Borsuk-Ulam t heorem

17

st at es t hat t here exists a point Á

0

such t hat for all k, 1 · k · K ¡ 1, one has:

¹

0k

0

) = ¹

0k

(¡ Á

0

) :

T herefore, given t hat hÁ

0

i = h¡ Á

0

i , hÁ

0

i divides ¢

S

int o two pieces of equal measure wit h respect t o t he dist ribut ions f ¢µ

k0

, for all k, 1 · k · K ¡ 1. Since by const ruct ion it also divides ¢

S

int o two pieces of equal measure wit h respect t o f ¢

P k

µ

k0

, it does so with respect t o f ¢µ

K0

. Hence t he proof for t he a0-governance.

To prove exist ence of s{ MSPEa1 one has t o choose a hyperplane t hat separat es ¢

S

int o two pieces of equal measure wit h respect t o the dist ribut ions f ¢µ

k

, for all k. The argument is more complicat ed because t he lat t er dist ribut ions are endogeneously de¯ ned.

Nevert heless, t he argument also relies on t he Borsuk-Ulam t heorem applied t o funct ions de¯ ned t hrough anot her principle. T his is post poned t o Appendix B. 2

4.2 Sym m et r ic densit i es

It is possible t o de¯ ne more general assumpt ions under which simple majority st able product ion equilibria exist for all four governances | i.e., Corollary 1 holds t rue. We de¯ ne symmet ric dist ribut ions of types: for all permut at ions ¾of f 1; : : : ; Sg, if ¼

¾

denot es t he vect or of probabilit ies: (¼

¾(1)

; : : : ; ¼

¾(S)

), t hen for all ¼, f (¼

¾

) = f (¼).

P r op osit ion 2

Assume that

f [

resp.

f ¢µ

0k for all

k

,

f ¢

P k

µ

0k

]

is symmetric over

¢

S, then s{ MSPEp0 and p1

[

resp. s{ MSPEa0, s{ MSPEa1

]

exist as soon as

K ¸ S=2

.

Proof

: Thanks t o Lemma 2, t his goes by proving t hat any hyperplane t hrough ¹ Y (as de¯ ned by equat ions (5)) cut s ¢

S

int o two equal part s, in t erms of shareholders (¯ rst

17See T heorem 3.2.7 in Lloyd (1978): Let D be a bounded, open, symmet ric subset of Rn cont aining 0;

let ¹ : @D ¡ ! Rm be cont inuous, and m < n; t hen t here is Á 2 @D such t hat ¹ (Á) = ¹ (¡ Á). Here D is t he unit ball, n = S¡ 1, @D ´ SS¡ 2, and m = S¡ 2: ¹ (Á) = (¹01(Á); : : : ; ¹0K ¡ 1(Á)). An illust rat ion is t hat t here exist two ant ipodal point s on t he eart h wit h same t emperat ure and pressure. See also Guillemin and Pollack (1974), pages 91-93.

(20)

assert ion of t he proposit ion) as well as in t erms of shares (second assert ion). Since K ¸ S=2, one has S = K + m wit h m · K . To any ¼, associat e it s symmet ric t hrough h¹ Y i :

¼

¿

= (¼

2

; ¼

1

; : : : ; ¼

2m

; ¼

2m ¡ 1

; ¼

2m+ 1

; : : : ; ¼

S

) :

Generically, ¼and ¼

¿

are strict ly on each side of h¹ Y i , and t hen will always count er-balance each ot her in any collect ive decision making under `one person-one vot e' governances.

Under t he assumpt ions of t he proposit ion t hey have t he same amount of shares of each

¯ rm, and will always count er-balance each ot her in any collect ive decision making under

`one share-one vot e' governances. 2

In fact , as easily seen from t he proof, much lighter assumpt ions of symmet ry can ensure t he result . Indeed, t he argument developed here shows some similarity with t he underlying analysis in Grandmont (1978): in t hat paper, exist ence of majority-st able equilibria (in t he case wit hout exchange: K = 1) was shown for cent rally-symmet ric support s of agent s' types. The present argument relies on t he same principle: t he simplex ¢

S

is symmet ric, not wit h respect t o a point , but wit h respect t o K -dimensional subspaces (wit h K ¸ S=2), and t he only needed assumpt ion is t hat t he dist ribut ions of charact erist ics be symmet ric wit h respect t o one of t hese subspaces

18

.

4.3 º -concave densi t ies

A density funct ion f is º -concave over ¢

S

if for all ¼; ¼

0

2 ¢

S

, 8¸ 2 [0; 1], f [(1 ¡ ¸ )¼+ ¸ ¼

0

] ¸ [(1 ¡ ¸ )f (¼)

º

+ ¸ f (¼

0

)

º

]

1=º

:

T his assumpt ion is regarded as imposing some measure of consensus in t he society. Not ice t hat for º = 1 , one get s t he uniform dist ribut ion of Sect ion 3. De¯ ne

19

:

½(S; º ) = 1 ¡

Ã

S ¡ 1 + 1=º S + 1=º

! S+ 1=º

:

Consider a PE (Y; 1

K

; µ). As in t he canonical case, ¯ nding a best challenger t o t he equilibrium product ion plan of a ¯ rm reduces t o try and cut t he support ¢

S

by an

18T here is t he implicit feat ure, in Caplin and Nalebu® (1988), t hat t he simplex is, as a support of vot ers' type, t he geomet rical shape t hat allows t he most uneven cut t ing t hrough t he cent er of gravity (see t he principle of symmet rizat ion of Schwart z on which t hey found t his feat ure): if an upper bound works for t he simplex, it works for any ot her convex support . T his feat ure might not be t rue anymore as far as cut t ing t he support t hrough a well-chosen K -dimensional subspace is concerned.

19T he rat io ½(S; º ) is bounded above by 1 ¡ 1=e when º ¸ 0.

(21)

hyperplane cont aining hY i in such a way as t o maximize t he di®erence in volume of t he two result ing pieces. When t he dist ribut ion of shareholders' voting weight s is exogeneously

¯ xed (as for t he p0, p1 and a0 governances), given t hat t he support of all considered dist ribut ions is convex, one can direct ly import Caplin and Nalebu® (1991) main result on º -concave dist ribut ion of charact erist ics t o get t he following proposit ion.

P r op osit ion 3

I f

f

is

º

-concave, then for

º ¸ ¡ 1=S

, any PE

(Y; 1

K

; µ)

such that

hY i

contains the mean shareholder' s type20

¼

g of distribution

f

is a

½(S; º )

{ MSPEp0 and p1.

I f

f ¢µ

0k is

º

-concave for all

k

, then for

º ¸ ¡ 1=S

, any PE

(Y; 1

K

; µ)

such that

hY i

contains the

K

mean shareholder types

gk

)

Kk= 1 of the

K

distributions

(f ¢µ

k0

)

Kk= 1 is a

½(S; º )

{ MSPEa0.

I n both cases, there exist a continuum of such

½(S; º )

{ MSPE.

It is clear t hat, for t he for t he `one person-one vot e' governances, t he higher K , t he smaller t he rat e of super-majority ½t hat is necessary t o guarantee t he exist ence of ½{

majority stable product ion equilibria. Indeed, on t op of having t o cut ¢

S

t hrough it s cent er of gravity, one can add as many const raint s as t here are ¯ rms, each added const raint lowering t he di®erence in size of t he two pieces result ing from t he cut t ing. We leave for furt her research act ual comput at ions of t he ext ent t o which t he subsequent rat e ½can be improved, i.e., by comput ing t he t rue

21

min-max ½(S; K ; º ). For t he a0-governance, one does not have t hese K ¡ 1 added const raint s on t he way t o cut t he simplex. It is easy t o prove in t hat set up t hat t he rat io ½(S; º ) cannot be improved for t he a0-governance.

When t he dist ribut ion of shareholders' vot ing weights is endogeneously det ermined by t he market mechanism from t he announced mult iplan Y , as for t he a1-governance, a result similar t o Proposit ion 3 is more di± cult t o obtain. One has t o prove t he exist ence of a PE (Y; 1

K

; µ) such t hat , for all k,

1. hY i cont ains, for all k, t he cent er of gravity of t he `equilibrium' dist ribut ion f ¢µ

k

; 2. f ¢µ

k

º -concave for some º .

T he following mult ivariat e mean shareholder t heorem can be proposed.

T heor em 3

I f the distribution

f ¢

Pk

µ

k0 is

º

-concave, then for

¡ 1=S · º · 1

, there exist

½(S; º )

{ MSPEa1.

20T he mean shareholder's type is t he one t hat lies at t he cent er of gravity of t he dist ribut ion; it is de¯ ned as: ¼g= (¼1g; : : : ; ¼Sg) wit h for all s: ¼gs =

Z

¢S

f (¼) ¼s d¼.

21For º = 1 , ½(S; K ; 1 ) = ½S;K as de¯ ned by (4).

(22)

Proof

: See Appendix B. In fact t he proof shows t hat t here are, generically wit h respect t o f ¢

P k

µ

0k

, up t o

0

@

S ¡ 1 K ¡ 1

1

A

di®erent subspaces hY i for which the theorem holds. 2 T his last result sheds some light on t he debat e on which object ive funct ion t he ¯ rm should opt imize in t he cont ext of incomplet e market s. Firm should make choices t hat are support ed by shareholders. In t he present set up, a shareholder is basically charact erized by it s type ¼, which can be ident i¯ ed as his ideal security. For example T heorem 3 shows existence of product ion equilibria which are st able for `accept able' rat es of super majority;

t hey are such t hat , for ¯ rm k, t he shareholder whose type, ¼

g;k

, is at t he cent er of gravity of t he equilibrium dist ribut ion of shares (i.e., t he above-ment ioned mean shareholder) can exact ly span it s type, and generat e it s ideal security: [

P`

µ

0`

g;k

)] ¢¼

g;k

; he could not do bett er if market s were complet e. But t o span his ideal security he needs, in general, t o buy

all

securit ies. (T he same line of reasoning holds for t he a0-governance t hrough Proposit ion 3.)

T his result has no direct link wit h t he Drµ eze crit erion. Indeed, t he announced se- curity/ production plan, y

k

, of ¯ rm k does not have to be t he ideal security/ product ion plan, ¼

g;k

, of this mean shareholder (in general, t he mult iplan Y , wit h y

k

= ¼

0g;k

cannot be support ed as a Paret o PE). But t he multiplan Y should be such t hat it cont ains t he ideal security of

all

mean shareholders; in some way t he mult iplan Y is opt imal for t he K mean shareholders. Then t he product ion equilibria are st able for t he lowest possible rat es of super majority. Finally, it is also t he case here t hat t he assumpt ions securing t he result are weaker for t he governances µ a la Drµ eze, i.e., based on post -t rade shares.

4.4 Ext ensi ons

I m m ediat e ext ension t o a br oader class of ut ilit y funct ions

As easily seen from the proof, t he exist ence of s-MSPE (for governances based on pre-t rade shares) in the case K = S ¡ 1 (or, t rivially, K = S) are st ill valid under assumpt ion (A) and t he assumpt ion t hat ¼= Argmax f U

¼

(x) j x 2 ¢

S

g. Indeed, given a PE (Y; 1

K

; µ), t he ¯ rst order conditions of agent s' maximizat ion programs give, for all k ¸ 2, all ¼:

D U

¼

[x(¼)] ¢(y

k

¡ y

1

) = 0 : (8)

Suppose K = S ¡ 1, when asked whet her t hey agree wit h an in¯ nit esimal change u 2 R

S

(which can be taken ort hogonal t o h¹ Y i , given equat ions (8)) in t he product ion plan of

Références

Documents relatifs

The capacity of hydroxyapatite (HAp) to remove lead from aqueous solution was investigated under different conditions, namely initial metal ion concentration and reaction time..

Une source d’ions produisant en particulier des ions He++ pour accélérateur

The strong non-linear but exponential increase of linewidth of Yb 3+ in CePd 3 is explained by an additional contribution to the relaxation of the 4f momentum due to a

We compare the density, energy and phase space density distribution of He+, O+ and Na+ from our model with observations from the MErcury Surface, Space ENvironment, GEochemistry,

The present observations are (i) preferential sputtering of the halogene atoms, (ii) temperature dependent sputter rates with 0.2 eV activation energy, (iii) sputter

The aim of this paper is to present no- theoretical data given by Griem /3/ as well ticed regularities of Stark broadening and as experimental ones obtained by Puri6 and

Rather than taking (KN) to be a positive truth requiring a truthmaker, the second proposal instead takes (KN) to be a derivative truth, itself lacking a truthmaker, yet whose truth

In the same time, these results show that a small insertion of Ta 2 O 5 (d=0.5 wt%) decreases the mass density of the obtained spinel ceramics. Our results indicate that this is