• Aucun résultat trouvé

Technical artefacts and perceptual experience

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "Technical artefacts and perceptual experience"

Copied!
3
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-00980521

https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00980521

Submitted on 18 Apr 2014

HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers.

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés.

Technical artefacts and perceptual experience

Armen Khatchatourov, John Stewart

To cite this version:

Armen Khatchatourov, John Stewart. Technical artefacts and perceptual experience. Enaction and enactive interfaces : a handbook of terms, Enactive Systems Books, pp.281-282, 2007. �hal-00980521�

(2)

Enaction and Enactive Interfaces: A Handbook of Terms 3

5+%7#'%$8!$-&+.$%&/!$#)!9+-%+9&:$8!

+;9+-'+#%+!

Armen Khatchatourov [COSTECH]

John Stewart [COSTECH]

The basic scheme for considering enaction is the dynamic sensory-motor coupling between an organism and its environment. The sensory inputs are used to guide the actions; the actions modify the environment and/or the relation of the organism to its environment, and hence modify in return the sensory input. This basic scheme applies already to animals. In the 1920’s the German ethologist von Uexküll [von Uexküll, 1966] characterized animal worlds (for example, the “world of the tick”) on the basis of sensori-motor contingencies as they function in ecological context.

What the world “is” for the organism amounts to neither more nor less than the consequences of its actions for its sensory inputs – what [O’Regan and Noe, 2001] call the sensori-motor contingencies; and this in turn clearly depends on the repertoire of possible actions. Without action, there is no “world”, and no perception.

There is a deep affinity between this ap- proach, the enactive approach of [Varela, 1991], and the ecological psychology of Gibson according to which perception is not a matter of computational representation, but rather a direct perception of affordances

!

!

"##$%&'()*+,, i.e. potential actions as such. This affinity lies, as we understand it, (a) in the fact that all of them assume a non- representationalist framework, and (b) in the fact that Gibsonian rules, laws of control

!

!

-$(.%$/01 /'2+1 $#, [Warren, 1988], contin- gencies !

!

3*(+$%45$.$%1 )$(.4(6*()71 $%1

&*8*(&*()7, [O’Regan and Noe, 2001], all of them are not pre-given but emerge from the interaction between an organism and its envi- ronment.

For the purposes of this text, we are not going any further in the description of (discre- pancies between) these approaches, we rather

propose to consider what is specific to human beings: technical artefacts.

One of the major characteristics of human worlds is that the sensory-motor coupling is mediated by technical artefacts. For animals, the sensory organs and the motor organs are fixed (within any given species), and they are attached to the body. For humans, the medi- ation of sensory-motor coupling by technical artefacts introduces two radical innovations.

Firstly, the range of possible sensory inputs and the repertoire of possible actions is greatly increased, without any limits other than the invention and fabrication of new artefacts. This is clear for the new possibilities of action which are created by tools, from hammers and screw- drivers to power-tools of many sorts. It is also clear for instruments – microscopes, tele- scopes, microphones, infra-red detectors, radios and so on resulting in sensory inputs which are strictly impossible without the de- vices in question. An interesting special case is the sensory substitution devices [Lenay, 1997].

More generally, but less obviously, technical artefacts

organize sensory experience: think of

the world of skier, which is impossible without the artefact. Even when we are not actually skiing, our perception of the mountain is de- termined by the possibility (i.e. virtual action) of skiing and the correlative sensations. So this first point can be understood more profoundly:

in case of contemporary humans, there hardly any "natural" perceptions or relations to the world: our sensory-motor coupling is always fashioned, at least virtually, by technical arte- facts [Khatchatourov, 2005].

Secondly, technical artefacts are not irre-

mediably fixed to the body. More precisely,

technical artefacts exist in two modes: in hand

and put down. When a technical artefact is in

hand, being used, it becomes a prosthetic

extension of the body; correlatively, the arte-

fact disappears from consciousness, and the

attention of the human subject is focussed on

the "world" that comes about (think again of

the "world of the skier", for example). Arte-

facts, like the body, are normally transparent

[Merleau-Ponty, 1945] to the subject; as

[Heidegger, 1996] has pointed out, they are

only noticed when they are dysfunctional (a

wobbly hammer or a twisted ankle). However,

(3)

4 Enaction and Enactive Interfaces: A Handbook of Terms

unlike biological organs, technical artefacts can also be "put down": separated from the body, they can now become objects of attention. In this mode, their objective physical proprieties can be perceived; they can be invented, fabrica- ted, repaired and so on [Lenay & Sebbah, 2001]. The whole question of learning can be seen as the back-and-forth movement between these two modes. This explains also the radical innovative potential of technical artefacts. Over several thousand years, and at an ever- increasing rate, technical innovation has radi- cally transformed what the world is for human beings.

<+.+-+#%+/!

[Heidegger, 1996] Heidegger, M., Being and Time, State University of New York Press, 1996.

[Khatchatourov, 2005]

Khatchatourov, A et Auvray, M.

L’outil modifie-t-il la perception ou la rend-il possible ? In Actes du Ve Colloque Jeunes Chercheurs en Sciences Cognitives, Paris, 2003;

and revue Arob@se, www.univ- rouen.fr/arobase, 2005.

[Lenay, 1997] Lenay, C. et al., Technology and Perception: the Contribution of Sensory Substitution Systems. In Second International Conference on Cognitive Technology, Aizu, Japan, Los Alamitos: IEEE, 1997, pp. 44-53.

[Lenay & Sebbah, 2001] Lenay C., Sebbah F., La constitution de la perception spatiale. Approches

phénoménologique et

expérimentale. in Intellectica, n°32, 2001/1

[Merleau-Ponty, 1945] Merleau-Ponty.

Phenoménologie de la perception.

Gallimard, Paris, 1945.

[O’Regan and Noe, 2001] O’Regan K.J. and Noë A., "A sensorimotor account of vision and visual

conciousness." In Behavioural and Brain Sciences 24, 2001, pp. 5-115.

[Varela, 1991] Varela F., Thompson E.

& Rosch E. The Embodied Mind. MIT Press, Boston, 1991.

[von Uexküll, 1966] von Uexküll J.V., Mondes animaux et monde humain. Gonthier, Paris, 1966.

[Warren, 1988] Warren, W. H., "Action modes and laws of control for the visual guidance of action." In O. G.

Meijer & K. Roth (Eds.), Complex movement behaviour: The motor- action controversy. Amsterdam:

North Holland. 1988, pp. 339-380.

<+8$&+)!'&+6/!

"##$%&'()*+1 -$(.%$/01/'2+1$#1

9(').4:*1)$6(4.4:*1+)4*()*+;<1 9=.*%('/4>'.4$(018*%)*8.?'/1

3*(+$%45$.$%1)$(.4(6*()71$%1&*8*(&*()71

3*(+$%71+?@+.4.?.4$(1

Références

Documents relatifs

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des

Within what known the knowledge economic the firms aware that the human resource is the whealth; and firms must make appropriate interest to their employee, and seek to

Being on the road, one does not consider the road as the physical proprieties of tarmac in the way the science/technology do, but rather as a possi- bility to get

is unknown whether muscle activation and/or muscle moment arm counteract these individual 90.. differences in PCSA such that the distribution of torque among the muscle

This last step does NOT require that all indicator be converted - best if only a small percent need to be reacted to make the change visible.. Note the

The artefact has a make plan, which allows reproducing more technical objects conforming to the artefact, as well as a use plan that specifies in which events and under which

With respect to LP, for instance, we propose   that   minimal   model   construction   accurately   models   people’s   cooperative interpretation of conditionals uttered

To introduce the concept of feedback in socio-technical systems, we use an example of software development project in its simplified form presented in the diagram of Fig..