• Aucun résultat trouvé

A nonstandard proof for Szpilrajn's theorem

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "A nonstandard proof for Szpilrajn's theorem"

Copied!
6
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-01279725

https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01279725

Submitted on 4 Mar 2016

HAL

is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire

HAL, est

destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires

A nonstandard proof for Szpilrajn’s theorem

Abdelmadjid Boudaoud

To cite this version:

Abdelmadjid Boudaoud. A nonstandard proof for Szpilrajn’s theorem. International Conference in

Mathematics 2012, Dr. Muhammed I. Syam, Mar 2012, Al - Ain (United Arab Emirates University

), United Arab Emirates. �hal-01279725�

(2)

A nonstandard proof for Szpilrajn’s theorem

Abdelmadjid BOUDAOUD

Pure and Applied Mathematics Laboratory (LMPA), Department of Mathematics,

Faculty of mathematics and Computer Sciences University of M’sila, Algeria.

E-mail : boudaoudab@yahoo.fr March 4, 2016

Abstract

Recall that Szpilrajn (1930) ([4], [5]) states that on a given set, any partial order can be extended to a total order on the same set. In this work we give, in the context of the IST theory ([2],[3],[6]), a more constructive proof for this theorem. In addition, we benefit of the tools used to give some other results.

Mathematics Subject Classification: 03E25, 03H05, 06A05

Keywords: Nonstandard Analysis, Axiom of Choice (AC), Total Order, Szpil- rajn’s theorem, Density.

1 Introduction

This paper is placed in the framework of IST ([2],[3],[6]), where to prove the result announced above in the abstract, the main tools are the use, instead of an infinite set X, of a finite subset F = {x1, x2, ..., xN} ⊂ X containing all standard elements of X, transfer principle and standardization principle. In addition, since we can construct several alternatives of linear order on a given set [1] , we give some other applications, which are Propositions 6, 7 and 8. Let us recall the Standardization principle : For all formulaF(Z) internal or external, we have:

stx∃sty∀stz[z∈y ⇐⇒ z∈xandF(z)] (S) where x is the referential set and y is a standard set which is the standard- ized of{z∈xandF(z)}. We puty ={z∈xand F(z)}s. Thus, by using the principle (S), we can associate a standard set for any given set. Hence, it is a principle of construction.

(3)

Definition 1 1) If T1 and T2 are subsets of a linearly ordered set, we call T1 strictly dense (resp. dense) in T2, if for every two elements a < b of T2 there exists an elementc∈T1 witha < c < b(resp. a≤c≤b).

2) LetA andB be a given sets. Ais called equivalent to B, written A∼B, if there exists a function f :A−→B which is one-one and onto.

Notation. Letn be a positive integer,n≈+∞denotes thatnis unlimited.

We need to recall that from the main result of [1] we immediately deduce Theorem 2 Let X be any infinite standard set, let G={β1, β2, ..., βN} ⊂X, (N ≈+∞)be a subset containing all the standard elements of X and let Ω = n

βi, βj

N≥i≥1, N≥j≥ii, βj∈Go

⊂X×X. Then, the relation defined byΩs fromX toX as follows

xy iff (x, y)∈Ωs is a standard total ordering on X.

2 Main results

Theorem 3 (Szpilrajn [1930]) [4]. Let (P,≤) be a poset. Then there exists a linear order≤ onP which contains≤, a so-called linear extension of ≤. In particular: ifaandbare incomparable elements, this linear order can be chosen in such a way thata≤b holds.

Proof. In order to prove this result we need the following lemmas whose proofs are without use AC [4].

Lemma 4 [[4], p. 53]. Let(P1, R1) be a poset,a andb two incomparable ele- ments ofP1. Then there exists an order relation Rf1 on P1 which contains R1 and in whichaRf1b holds.

Lemma 5 [[4],, p. 27] . Every order R2 on a finite set P2 is a subset of a linear order on this set. In other words: Every order relation on a finite set is extendible to a linear order.

Hence, lemma 5 is a partial statement of the theorem of Szpilrajn.

Return to the proof in question. By transfer, we may assume thatP,≤,a andbare standard. We distinguish the two following cases.

A)Pis finite. By lemma 4, there exists an order relation≤eonPwhich contains

≤and in whichae≤bholds. Now, by lemma 5there exists a linear order ≤eewhich

(4)

contains≤. By takinge ≤ee for≤, we finish the proof for this case. Indeed,since ee

≤isa linear order,≤is also. Since≤⊂≤ ⊂e ≤ee =≤,≤ contains≤. Moreover, the fact thata≤be entails, since≤ ⊂e ≤,ee a≤bee i.e. a≤b.

B) P is infinite. Let P1 = {y1, y2, ..., yN} be a finite subset of P containing all standard elements of P, where N is necessarily an unlimited integer. In particular,aandb belong toP1, since they are standard. Now, let us consider the poset (P1,≤↑P1) and denote the order ≤↑P1 byR1, where ≤↑ P1 is the restriction of≤toP1.

Then by lemma 4 there exists an order relationRf1onP1 which containsR1 and in whichaRf1b holds. Again, by lemma 5 there exists a linear orderR on P1 which containsRf1. ThenaRb.

Since (P1, R) is a chain, we can putP1={x1, x2, ..., xN}(xi ∈ {y1, y2, ..., yN} for 1≤i≤N), such thatx1Rx2,x2Rx3,x3Rx4,...,xN1RxN. We notice here thata(resp. b) corresponds toxi1 (resp. toxi2), wherei1,i2are in{1,2, ..., N}

withxi1Rxi2 sinceaRf1b. Let G=n

(xi, xj)N≥i≥1, N≥j≥i|xi, xj∈P1

obe the graph of (P1, R), where saying that (xi, xj) ∈ G is the same to saying that xiRxj. Let Gs ⊂ P ×P be the standardization of G. It is known that Gs defines a relation Γ fromP to P as follows

xΓy iff (x, y)∈Gs. According to theorem 2, Γ is a total order onP.

Now, we prove the remainder of the theorem. Let (x, y)∈P2 be a standard element verifyingx≤y. Then we have successively xR1y, xfR1y, xRy. Then (x, y)∈Gand therefore (x, y)∈Gsbecause (x, y) is standard. Hence xΓy. So

st(x, y)∈P2[(x≤y) =⇒xΓy] .

Then by transfer, ∀(x, y)∈P2[(x≤y) =⇒xΓy]. Hence, Γ contains ≤. From what precedes, we have concerning (a, b): aRb. This shows that (a, b)∈Gi.e.

(a, b)∈ Gs since (a, b) is standard. Consequently, aΓb. Now, by taking Γ for

we finish the proof for this case. By transfer, we conclude for allP.

Proposition 6 LetX be any set. Suppose thatAandB are nonempty disjoint subsets ofX. Then we can provideX by a total ordering such that

∀x, y∈X[(x∈Aandy∈B) =⇒ xy]. Proof. By transfer, we supposeX,AandB are standard. Let

F ={β1, β2, ..., βN} ⊂X

be a finite subset containing all standard elements of X. Suppose that this numbering of elements ofF has been made so that elements ofA∩F are before those ofB∩F. Now, by theorem 2 and transfer we finish the proof.

(5)

Proposition 7 LetX be any set. LetS be a system of mutually disjoint subsets ofX. Then we can provideX by a total ordering such that

∀A, B∈S[A < B or B < A].

Proof.Assume, by transfer, thatXandSare standard. LetF ={x1, x2, ..., xω1}, ω1∼= +∞(resp. S ={A1, A2, ..., Aω2},ω2∼= +∞) be a finite subset ofX (resp.

ofS) containing all standard elements ofX (resp. ofS). Forj= 1,2, ..., ω2, we put

F∩Aj=

yj,1, yj,2, ..., yj,nj

which is a finite set containing all standard elements of Aj. Put L = F \

ω2

j=1(F∩Aj) ={y1, y2, ..., ys}.

Now, we rearrange elements ofFas follows : We begin by elements ofF∩A1, after those ofF∩A2, after those ofF∩A3 and so on. ThusF becomes

F =

y1,1, y1,2, ..., y1,n1, y2,1, y2,2, ..., y2,n2, ..., yω2,1, yω2,2, ..., yω2,nω2

∪ {y1, y2, ..., ys} where

ω2

P

j=1

nj+s=ω1. Now, by theorem 2 and transfer we finish the proof.

Proposition 8 LetX andY be any sets. IfX ∼Y then we can provide X∪Y by a total ordering such thatX becomes strictly dense inY.

Proof. By transfer, we may assume thatX andY are standard. SinceX ∼Y then there exists a mappingϕ:Y −→X which is one-one and onto. By transfer ϕis standard. Let FY ={y1, y2, ..., yN} be a finite subset ofY containing all standard elements of Y. Then ϕ[FY] = {ϕ(y1), ϕ(y2), ..., ϕ(yN)} is a finite subset ofX containing all standard elements ofX. Let us put

FX∪Y = {y1, ϕ(y1), y2, ϕ(y2), y3, ϕ(y3), y4, ϕ(y4), ..., ϕ(yN1), yN, ϕ(yN)} .

ThenFX∪Y is a finite subset ofX∪Y containing all the standard elements of X∪Y. As well as in the theorem 2, we construct from FX∪Y the setG and thereafter the setGswhich is a standard linear order inX∪Y.

Let yi andyj be standard elements ofY such that yi ≺yj in Gs which is equivalent toi < j. Then we haveyi < ϕ(yi)< yj, whereϕ(yi) is a standard element ofX. Therefore

st(α, β)∈Y2stγ∈X[α < β =⇒ α < γ < β] .

Which, by transfer, entails∀(α, β)∈Y2∃γ∈X [α < β =⇒ α < γ < β]. Con- sequentlyX is strictly dense inY, where X andY are subsets ofX∪Y which is linearly ordered byGs.

(6)

References

[1] A. Boudaoud, Existence of a total Order in Every set, Journal of Mathe- matics and Statistics,120(2012), 195-197.

[2] I.P. Van den Berg, Extended use of IST,Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, North Holland,58(1992), 73-92.

[3] F. Diener and G. Reeb,Analyse non-standard, Hermann, Editeurs des Sci- ences et des Arts, Cambridge, 1989.

[4] Egbert Harzheim,Ordered sets, Springer, 2005.

[5] Karel Hrbacek and Thomas Jech,Introduction to set theory, Marcel Dekker, Inc. New York Basel, Springer, 1999.

[6] E. Nelson, internal set theory, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc., 83(1977), 1165- 1198.

Références

Documents relatifs

Thus, hedefi ned the multiplication of two cardinal numbers 1, and, although the extension of this definition to a transfinite number of cardinal numbers

• Even if the destination endpoint doesn’t speak MPLS, the LSP that goes to the last MPLS speaking router along the path will be

This is a photochromic compound that, when irradiated in the open form with UV light (320–370 nm) undergoes a photocyclization reaction, giving a coloured compound, ther- mally

For the same implication with Property FM’, it is convenient to first observe that a topological group G has Property FM’ if and only if for every continuous discrete G-set

The problem of deciding the existence of a SEPI from G to G’ is NP-complete, but show that when G is fixed, this problem can be decided in constant-time (hint: this

One way out of this difficulty was indicated in [2], and has been recently recalled in [6, 9]: If one managed to prove that there are only a finite number of solutions to a

At that time the com­ pany, under the direction of Peter Z inovieff, was exploring the possibilities of using mini­ computers to control electronic music instruments.. My job was

In this chapter, we study the Korteweg-de Vries equation subject to boundary condition in non-rectangular domain, with some assumptions on the boundary of the domain and