• Aucun résultat trouvé

Contributions to foundations of probability calculus on the basis of the modal logical calculus <span class="mathjax-formula">$MC^\nu $</span> or <span class="mathjax-formula">$MC^\nu _\ast $</span>

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Partager "Contributions to foundations of probability calculus on the basis of the modal logical calculus <span class="mathjax-formula">$MC^\nu $</span> or <span class="mathjax-formula">$MC^\nu _\ast $</span>"

Copied!
9
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

R ENDICONTI

del

S EMINARIO M ATEMATICO

della

U NIVERSITÀ DI P ADOVA

A. M ONTANARO A. B RESSAN

Contributions to foundations of probability calculus on the basis of the modal logical calculus MC

ν

or MC

ν

Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico della Università di Padova, tome 65 (1981), p. 263-270

<http://www.numdam.org/item?id=RSMUP_1981__65__263_0>

© Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico della Università di Padova, 1981, tous droits réservés.

L’accès aux archives de la revue « Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico della Università di Padova » (http://rendiconti.math.unipd.it/) implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www.numdam.org/conditions).

Toute utilisation commerciale ou impression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit conte- nir la présente mention de copyright.

Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques

http://www.numdam.org/

(2)

Probability

on

the Basis of the Modal Logical Calculus MCv

or

MCv*.

A. MONTANARO - A. BRESSAN

(*)

PART 2

On

a Known

Existence Rule for the Probability Calculus.

8. Introduction

(**)

By

means of the

probability calculus,

and

precisely

its formula-

tion

PC* [PC]

based on Part

I,

N. 5-we can cal-

culate the values of certain relative

probabilities,

such

under certain

conditions,

e.g. when we know the values of certain other

probabilities,

e.g. and Thus we can also deduce the existence of some

probabilities.

However the need of

asserting

the existence of various other

probabilities

was felt. There- fore the so called existence rule was formulated. For instance the

philosopher

Reichenbach states it as follows:

RULE 8.1. «If the numerical value p of a

probability implication (A

31)

B), provided

the

probability implication exists,

is determined

(*)

Indirizzo

degli

A.A.: Istituto di Analisi e Meccanica, Via Belzoni 7, 35100 Padova.

(**)

Bressan’s contribution to this work

belongs

to the

sphere

of

activity

of the C.N.R.

(Consiglio

Nazionale delle

Ricerche)

in the academic years 1978-79 and 1979-80.

The summary of this paper is included in the one of Part I, i.e.

[2].

(3)

264

by given probability implications according

to the rules of the

calculus,

then this

probability implication (A 3, B)

exists » cf.

[4]

p. 53

(1).

This rule is

substantially

used also

by

some

probabilists,

e.g.

by

Dore-cf.

[3]

p. 66. Such rules are said to be

metalogical by

all users

of them-cf. the

preceding

f ootnote-and even

ineta-probabilistic by

some of them

(2).

Let us add that these formulations also have an

intuitive and not very

precise

character.

By

the reasons

above,

in

[1]

the existence

rule,

a

logic-probabi-

listic rule on a

pair

with inference rules such as modus ponens, is

replaced

with an

(existence)

axiom

scheme,

as a

proposal

to be tested.

In the

present

paper the afore-inentioned axiom scheme is con-

sidered-cf. A9.1 and it is hinted at its reduction to an

admittedly

more

complex single axiom,

A9.1’ which is

meaningful

also in

Then the test of A9.1

proposed

in

[I],

is

performed

with a

positive

result. A

precise

existence

rule,

Rule

10.1, strictly

weaker than

A9.1,

is derived from this axiom scheme in PC*

[PC] ;

and the main exist-

ence assertions

ordinarily

reached on the basis of the intuitive Rule

8.1,

-cf.

[2]-,

, are

rigorously

and

explicitly

derived

by

the new rule.

The

probability

calculus PC*

[PC] supplemented

with A9.1

[A9.1’]

will be called the

probability theory

PT*

[PT].

9. On a

rigorous

axiom scheme in that can

replace

Rule

8.1,

and a

single

axiom

equivalent

to it.

In order to formulate the axiom scheme A9.1

below,

to be sub-

stituted for Rule

8.1,

we consider the

following

conditions

(c~)

to

which refer to

(1)

In [4], p. 53, Reichenbach says about Rule 8.1: «The rule of existence is not an axiom of the calculus; it is a rule formulated in the

metalanguage, analogous

to the rule of inference or the rule of substitution.

It must be

given

an

interpretation

even in the formal treatment of the

calculus. There must exist a formula that can be demonstrated in the cal- culus and that expresses the

probability

under consideration as a mathema- tical function of the

given probabilities,

with the

qualification

that the func-

tion be

unique

and free from

singularities

for the numerical values used.

This is what is meant

by

the

expression

"determined

according

to the

rules of the calculus" &#x3E;&#x3E;.

(2) In [3], p. 53, about the existence rule it is said that its

metalogical

and

metaprobabilitistic

character is evident, and that its basis must be found in the intuitive content of the

concept

of

probability.

(4)

(a)

al to OCn

(n ~ 0)

are distinct

propositional variables,

(b)

p, to pm and

(m ~ 0,

It &#x3E;

0)

are distinct variables

of type tR,

the

type of

real

numbers;

and

where ri , si, orj, 7:j ... ,

for

i =

1,

... , m

and j

=

1,

... , ,u ;

(c) ~a

is any assertion

equivalent

to and built

by

means

of only

«1 to «n, ~,

/~, 0,

and

parentheses (so

that pi, 1aei, and vi ’v’

fail

to occur in

8a);

(d) Ðp

is an assertion

equivalent

to that

belongs

to the

theory

RT

of

real numbers and contains no variables

different f rom

PI to pm . Now we can formulate the existence axiom stated in

[1].

A9.1

(existence)

Intuitively,

y

by (a)

to

(d),

A9.1 means the

following:

Let us consider

(i)

a mathematical condition

Ðp

on the real

numbers p 1 to p m c . g. p 1

+

P2

c 1

,

( ii )

the

conditions ya

and

on the

propositional

variables a1 to ocn and the real-valued vari- ables PI to pm and it, to use, defined

by (9.1), (iii)

a

non-contingent (modally constant)

condition

~a

on

only

ccl to an, that can be

expressed

in the

(modal) propositional calculus,

and

(iv)

the

assumptions A)

conditions

~p.,

Ya’ and

~a- hold,

B)

can, occurs

(j

=

1,

...,

p),

and

C) if

conditions

6

and

also hold,

then

~c~

_

uff

Assumptions A)

to

0) necessarily imply

the existence

of

real

bers Ul to Up, such that

implies

with the

probability

Uj

(i

=

1,

...,

!l).

In

XC’*

A5.r can be

regarded

as a

single

axiom

(r

=

1,

... ,

8)

whereas A9.1 is

necessarily

an axiom scheme. In order to reduce it

(5)

266

briefly

to a

single

axiom

(meaningful

also in in connection with

(a)

we use a variable A of

type (tN) (capable

of

expressing

prop- erties of natural

numbers).

In connection with

( b )

we introduce in

the class

formed

by

the

mappings f

of

type (tN: N),

I such that for and

f (x)

= a* otherwise. We can define

in a similar way. Then

(9.1)

can be

replaced by

In connection with

(c), first,

we consider the additional variables

v1L,

m, and q, of the

respective types (tN), tN,

and

second,

we

introduce a substitutum for

6« by setting

In connection with

(d)

we consider R as a constant of MOv

(hence

of that expresses the natural absolute

concept

of real

numbers ;

furthermore we

replace Ðp

with

Ðp,3t,m where p,

and m are vari-

ables of the

respective types

and

tN,

and where

Now we can

replace

axiom scheme A9.1 with the

equivalent single

axiom

(in

(6)

10. A

precise

existence rule derived from A9.1.

Application

of it to

prove some fundamental existence theorems.

In the

theory

PT * = PC*

+

A9.1 we derive the

following

RULE 10.1

(existence).

Assume that

(i)

ya, and the vari- ables a1 to an and Ul to un conditions

(a)

to

(d)

in N.

9, (ii) fli

to

~8n (E

and v, to vn

(E EtR)

are other distinct

variables, (iii)

are

obtained

f rom by

the

replacement of

ai and u, f with

Pi

and v;

respectively (i

=

1,

... ,

m; j

=

1,

... , p;

u n)

and

(iv)

under abbrevia- tions such as

we have

(10.2)

Then

PROOF OF RULE 10.1. A9.1 is

equivalent

to

D

(3 u)

where 93 =D

(~~1~~)(~al,

...,

6~z By

the deduction

theorem, (10.2) implies

~6.

Now we prove the existence theorems

(10.4, 6)

below:

PROOF. Set al = a, a2

= fl,

a3 = y and a4 = With a view to

applying

Rule

10.1,

we set

In the we

easily

obtain

by ( 6.1 ) 1,

whence

hence

(10.4)1

holds.

Now we consider the case &#x3E;a1 and assume the antecedent oaf D

(7)

268

in

(10.4)1.

Then

by

the choice rule

(for

some a4, as, pl, and

P2)

we

obtain Furthermore

by Qal, 6,,

and

(6.3) 1

we obtain

Then, by (10.5)

and

A5.6,

from

Ba, Ya

and

~au

we

deduce P2

+

u.

Analogously,

from the

assumptions Yp, 3*v

and

Of3l

we deduce P2 = ~1

-~- v

whence u = v.

Thus

(10.2) holds,

and

by

Rule

10.1,

y,,, and

~au yield ( ~ ~ ) ~~~ ,

which

by (10.5)4

is a13 a3. Thus

(10.4)1

has been

proved.

For

it

yields (10.4)2.

PROOF. Indeed if - then

ocp 9

y

by (6.1)1’

so that

(10.6)1

holds.

Now we assume and with a view to

applying

Rule 10.1 we set

We also assume the antecedent of D in

(10.6)1’

hence

by

the choice

rule,

for some «4 ,

and p2

we have

Dp, Ea, ya,

and

01XU.

Fur-

thermore

by 6,.,

and

(6.3)I,

we have

(3lu)(a5

3u

(3).

Then

by

A5.7 and

(10.7),

6ex and ya

yield Similarly

from

Ð1n

ya,

~~ 8~

and we deduce pl v = ~4 . Then since

Pl=F 0,

Thus

(10.2) holds,

which

by

Rule 10.1

yields (10.3).

Hence

Ðp 6CBYa yields

a5 3u a3. We conclude that

(10.6)1

holds. We can prove

(10.6),

in a

quite

similar way.

q.e.d.

By (10.4)2

we deduce the first of the theorems

from

(6.2)1,

the second from

A5.5,

and the third from A5.4.

(8)

ll. Version in or of some theorems of

probability

calculus.

Stochastic

independence.

We formulate a definition of stocastic

independence

in TP*

[TP]

and some theorems connected with it. We do not write their formal

(modal) proofs

because it is easy to write them on the basis of NN. 9-10 and the

corresponding ordinary

mathematical

proofs.

THEOR. 11.1. Assume that ,...,

c ~y,

~

y~,

and that Y is

a matrix built

by

means

of fl,

y, ~,

A

7 and

parentheses;

and set

then

define SI (a, fl, y),

y is

stocastically independent of ~8

with

respect

to a,

by

where

For B and y

as in Theor.

11.1,

one can prove that

BIBLIOGRAFIA

[1] A. BRESSAN, Generalizations

of

the modal calculi MCv and MC~. Their

comparison

with similar calculi endowed with

different

semantics.

Applica-

tion to

probability theory,

in the

proceedings

of the

workshop

on modal

logic

held in

Tübingen

in Dec. 1977, i.e.

"Aspects

of

Philosophical Logic",

edited

by

U.

Mönnich, Synthese Library

Series, Dr. Reidel

Publishing

Co., Dordrecht

Holland/Boston (1981),

pp. 21-66.

(9)

270

[2] A. BRESSAN - A.

MONTANARO,

Contributions to

foundations of probability

calculus on the basis

of

the modal

logical

calculus MCv

or MCv* -

Part I:

Basic theorems

of

a recent modal version

of

the

probability

calculus, based

on MCv or

MCv*,

Rend. Sem. Mat. Univ. Padova, 64

(1980),

p. 11.

[3] P.

DORE,

Introduzione al calcolo delle

probabilità,

Patron,

Bologna

1962.

[4]

H. REICHENBACH, The

theory of probability. An inquiry

into the

logical

and mathematical

foundations of

the calculus

of probability, University

of

California Press,

Berkeley

and Los

Angeles,

1949.

Manoscritto

pervenuto

in redazione il 12 dicembre 1980.

Références

Documents relatifs

C~(T) ) est l'algèbre des applications continues (resp. continues et bornées) de T dans le corps des nombres réels IR.. c'CO ) muni de la topologie de la convergence compacte.

X** with the finite topology, by considering X * * as a subset of the topological space endowed with the direct product topology,.. where M is endowed with the discrete

An Analysis of the Notions of Random Variables and Probability Spaces, Based on Modal

Si s est modérément ramifiée, elle est induite d’un caractère modérément ramifié Il de l’extension quadratique non ramifiée de F, à. valeurs dans

The Poincaré-Birkhoff-Witt theorem and the Verma module construction In this section we construct a basis for d q and Pol(Uq(n)) by proving a Poincaré-.. Birkhoff-Witt

Soit (n, V) une représentation irréductible de G ayant un caractère central, et de dimension infinie.. Les fonctions de Kirillov

Mori [Mr] asserts the existence of a minimal model for a given complex algebraic 3-fold except for uniruled ones.. In [My] the author proved a minimal 3-fold has

Toute utilisation commerciale ou impression systématique est constitutive d’une infrac- tion pénale.. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la présente mention