• Aucun résultat trouvé

Reflexivity

Dans le document manuscript (Page 79-83)

In this section, we will relate the theory of lcs with the fundamental equation of classical Linear Logic, that is the fact that a formula is equivalent to its double linear negation:

A»AKK.

This corresponds to reflexivity in denotational semantics based on lcs.:

E»E2.

Note that the above linear homeomorphisms depends on the topology ofE (which determinesE1),and on the topology ofE1(which determinesE2).

Definition 3.5.1. ConsiderBa bornology onE(see Definition3.4.6). A lcs is said to besemi-B-reflexiveif ιE :

#EãÑE

xÞÑevx:p`ÞÑ`pxqq (3.5)

defines a linear isomorphismsE „ pEB1q1. It is said to beB-reflexiveif moreover the topologies ofE andE2 corresponds, that is ifE» pEB1q1B.

The restriction linear morphismιEis well defined:evxis continuous onEB1.

As the strong topology is the most common topology on the dual, we will by default call semi-reflexivity and reflexivity what is defined above as semi-β-reflexivity andβ-reflexivity. In particular Chapter7deals with strong reflexivity.

3.5.1 Weak, Mackey and Arens reflexivities

In this section we expose some classes of topology on the dual for which semi-reflexivity always holds. We already showed that every lcs is semi-σ-reflexive (Proposition3.3.13):E „ pE1 q1, and that any space endowed with its weak topology isσ-reflexive:Ew» pE1 q1.

This is also true for the Mackey-topology, whose role is symmetric to that of the weak topology (see the funda-mental Mackey-Arens Theorem3.5.3).

Proposition 3.5.2. Every lcs is semi-µ-reflexive:

E„ pE1µq1, and any space endowed with its Mackey topology isµ-reflexive:

EµpE1q» pEµ1q1µ.

Proof. Let us remark that the second linear homeomorphism follows directly form the first one: the Mackey topology onEis the topology of uniform convergence on absolutely convex compact sets inEσpEq1 . IfEis semi-µ-reflexive, theσpE1, EqandσpE1,pEµ1q1qcompact sets coincide, and thus the Mackey topology induced byE1 onEcoincides with Mackey topology induced byE1onE„ pEµ1q1.

Let us prove the first equality. It follows from the fact that pEσ1q „ E and from the fact that the Mackey topology is finer than the weak one (every finite subset is indeed weakly compact) that we have a continuous injection:Eµ1 ãÑEσ1. Its transpose results in a linear inclusion:

E„ pEσ1q1ãÑ pEµ1q1. (3.6)

Let us prove that it is surjective. ConsiderφP pEµ1q1. Asφis continuous, there exists a0-neighborhoodV in Eµ1 such that for every`PV,|φp`q| ă1. By definition of the Mackey topology, this means we have an absolutely weakly* compact subsetK ofE such that we can takeV “ K˝. This means that if we denote by p¨ ¨ ¨ q the polar in the dual pairppEµ1q1, E1,qwe haveφP K‚‚. Kcan indeed be considered as a subset ofpEµ1q1 through the linear injection. However, thanks to the bipolar theorem3.4.1, we have thatK‚‚ is the absolutely convex σppEµ1q1, E1q-closed closure ofKinpEµ1q1. AsKisσpE, E1q-compact it is in particularσppEµ1q1, E1q-compact and thusσppE1µq1, E1q-closed. As is it moreover absolutely convex, we haveK“K‚‚. AsKis a subset ofE, we obtainφPE.

This proposition implies in particular that for any topology T onE1 which is finer than the weak topology and coarser than the Mackey-topology, we havepET1 q1 „ E. This is proved by taking the double duals of the continuous injections:Eσ1 ãÑET1 ãÑEµ1. But we have more:

Theorem 3.5.3. The weak topology onE1is the coarsest locally convex Hausdorff vector topologyT such that pET1 q1“E, and the Mackey-topology is the finest.

Proof. LetT be a locally convex Hausdorff vector topology on E1 such that pET1 q1 “ E. Then in particular any evalutation functionevx : E1 //Kis continuous onET1 , thusT contains all the polars of the finite sets, and is finer than the weak topology. Moreover, we know that the topologyT is also the topology of uniform convergence on equicontinuous sets ofpET1 q1 “E(Proposition3.4.18). Thus any polarV˝of a0-neighborhood V inT is an equicontinuous set of E, thus is absolutely convex and weakly*-closed by the Alaoglu-Bourbaki theorem3.4.5. Therefore any closed absolutely convex0-neighborhoodV “V˝˝ofT is a0-neighborhood for the Mackey-topology. AsT is also generated by its closed0-neighborhood3.1.5, we have thatT is coarser than the Mackey-topology onE1.

Remark 3.5.4. In particular, any Mackey-dual is endowed with its Mackey-topology. Indeed, aspEµpEq1 q1 „E by proposition3.5.2, we have thatEµpEq1 , which is endowed byµpE1, Eqby definition, is also endowed with its Mackey-topologyµpE1, E2q. With respect to what is done in the case of weak topologies, the topologyµpE1, Eq onE1should be called the Mackey* topology.

We now detail the stability properties of the weak and Mackey topologies:

Proposition 3.5.5. [44, 8.8]

• The weak topology on a projective limit of lcs is the projective limit of the weak topologies.

• The Mackey topology of an inductive limit of lcs is the inductive limit of the Mackey topologies.

• The dual of an injective limit of lcs islinearly isomorphicto the dual of the projective limit.

• [44, 8.8.11] The Mackey dual of a Haussdorf injective limit of lcslinearly homeomorphicto the projective limite of the duals endowed with their respective Mackey topologies.

Theorem3.5.3has an important corollary:

Corollary 3.5.6. IfEτ1 is endowed with any topology comprised between the weak topologyσpE1, Eqand the Mackey-topologyµpE1, Eq, then the dual ofE1isE.

Proof. It follows from the hypothesis onEthat we have continuous linear injectionsEw1 ãÑEτ1 ãÑEµ1. Taking the dual of these injections gives linear mapsE //pE1τq1 //E. These maps are surjective by the Hahn Banach theorem, and thus leads to a linear isomorphismpEτ1q1„E.

In particular, as the Arens topology (see Definition3.4.16) satisfies this hypothesis:

Corollary 3.5.7. Any lcsEis semi-γ-reflexive, that is we have the linear isomorphism:pEγ1q1“E.

Thus the Arens dual acts as the Mackey dual or the weak dual in terms of semi-reflexivity. We also have that an Arens dual is alwaysγ-reflexive, meaning that we have a closure operator:

Proposition 3.5.8. For any lcsE, we have

Eγ1 » ppEγ1q1γq1γ.

Proof. This proof is done for example by Schwartz at the beginning of [67]. We already have the linear isomor-phism by the previous corollary. Let us show that the two spaces in the isomorisomor-phism have the same topology.

Consider any lcsF. Then the topology ofpFγ1q1γ “ F induces onF the topology of uniform convergence on absolutely convex and compact subsets ofFγ1, whileFis originally endowed with the topology of uniform conver-gence on equicontinuous subsets ofF1. Without loss of generality,Fis also endowed with the topology of uniform convergence on weakly closed equicontinuous subsets ofF1. But by the Alaoglu-Bourbaki theorem3.4.5, weakly closed equicontinuous sets are in particular weakly compact. As compact sets are weakly-compact, the topology ofpFγ1q1γ is always finer than the one ofF.

However, whenF “Eγ1, then equicontinuous subsets ofF1are by definition generated by the bornologyγpE, E1q, and thereforeEγ1 » ppEγ1q1γq1γ.

3.5.2 Strong reflexivity

In the literature, reflexivity is usually defined with respect to the strong dual: the terms reflexive and semi-reflexive are used for β-reflexive and semi-β-reflexive. Let us describe how β-reflexivity can be understood through a description of the topology of E. The proof makes use of all the notion introduced above, relying on a fine understanding of the role played by the weak and Mackey-topology, and of when a space is endowed with these topologies.

Proposition 3.5.9. [44, 11.4.1] The following propositions are equivalent:

1. Eis semi-β-reflexive,

2. The strong topology and the Mackey topology onE1coincide:Eβ1 »Eµ1, 3. Ewis quasi-complete, that is every bounded Cauchy-filter converges weakly.

Proof. p1q ô p2q: As the strong topology is finer than the Mackey topology3.4.15, and by the Mackey-Arens theorem3.5.3, as soon as a spaceE is semi-β-reflexive its dual E1 is endowed with its Mackey-topology. The converse follows immediately from the preceding Section3.5.1.

p2q ô p3q: IfEβ1 is endowed with its Mackey topology, it means that every bounded sets inE is weakly-compact, and in particular weakly complete. Conversely, if every bounded setBis weakly complete, from Propo-sition3.1.25it follows that its weak-closure is weakly-compact, and thus that the strong topology is coarser than the Mackey topology. As a weakly-compact set is always weakly-bounded, thus bounded by Proposition3.4.10, the Mackey topology is always coarser than the strong topology and we havep2q ð p3q.

In terms of polarized linear logic, semi-reflexivity is a negative characterization: it is preserved by projective limits, and particular cases by inductive limits:

Proposition 3.5.10. [44, 11.4.5] Semi-reflexivity of lcs is preserved by closed subspaces, projective limits and direct sums.

As semi-β-reflexivity can be modelled through a completeness condition, there exists a closure operator which makes anyE-semi-reflexive: the quasi-completion of Eis semi-β-reflexive and enjoys a functorial property as described in Proposition 3.1.24. Obtaining reflexivity requires much more, and there exists no general closure operator for reflexivity in the context of lcs.

A semi-reflexive lcsE is reflexive if and only ifE carries the same topology aspE1βq1β, that is the topology of uniform convergence on bounded subsets ofEβ1. Those are exactly the uniformly bounded subsets ofE1, that is the sets of functions sending uniformly a bounded set on a bounded set. AsE carries the topology of uniform convergence on equicontinuous subsets ofE1(Proposition3.4.18), we have:

Proposition 3.5.11. A semi-reflexive space is reflexive if and only if the equicontinuous subsets ofE1 and the uniformly bounded ones coincide.

In particular, let us recall from Section3.4.4that a lcs is barreled if and only if it is endowed with the topology βpE, E1q, that is the topology of uniform convergence on weakly-bounded sets ofE1. This topology is exactly the one induced by the strong bidualpEβ1q1βonE. Thus:

Proposition 3.5.12. A semi-reflexive lcsEis reflexive if and only if it is barreled.

Thus reflexivity combines a positive requirement (barreledness, stable by inductive limits) and a negative require-ment (semi-reflexivity, stable by projective limits). This gives some intuition about where the difficulty lies for finding good models ofLLmade of reflexive spaces.

Proposition 3.5.13. [44, 11.4.5] Reflexivity is preserved by cartesian products, direct sums, and strong duality.

ConsiderpEjqjan inductive system which is reduced (i.e. such that the mapsSk,jare injective) and such that the Ejare all reflexive. LetE“lim

ÝÑjEjbe the inductive limit of thepEjq. Then if for every bounded subsetBĂE, there existsjsuch thatBis a bounded subset ofEj, thenEis reflexive.

The following characterization is at the heart of Section7.2.2. From the fact that a metrisable lcs is barreled3.4.24, it follows that:

Proposition 3.5.14. [44, 11.34.3] ConsiderEa metrisable lcs. Then ifEis semi-β-reflexive, it isβ-reflexive and complete.

Outlook4. In a model ofMLL, we will be looking for conditions allowing for reflexivity which are preserved by tensor product. This requires finding a closure operator which makes a space reflexive (to use the Weak, Mackey or Arens dual), or to use a characterization restrictive enough so that it is preserved by some tensor product (as nuclearity, see Chapter7). But even before that, one must choose the topology on the tensor product, and see under which condition this tensor product is associative. This is the content of the next Section3.6.

3.5.3 The duality of linear continuous functions

This short subsection is essential. It provides tools for proving adjunctions of the typeLpE1, Fq »LpF1, Eqwhen Eis reflexive for some notion of reflexivity, thus constructing chiralities and models ofMLL. Consider a linear continuous functionf :E //F. Then by precomposition we obtain a linear functionf1 :F1 //E1. For which topologies isf1continuous ? The next proposition sums up results which are easy consequences of Section3.5.1.

Proposition 3.5.15. [44, 8.6.5]

Considerf : E //F linear. Thenf˚ :F˚ //E˚induces a linear mapf1 :F1 //E1 if and only iff is weakly continuous (i.e continuous with respect to the weak topology onEandF, i.e. continuous with respect to weak* topology onF and any topology onEcompatible with the dualE1). In that casef1is weakly* continuous.

Proof. The functionf is weakly continuous if and only iffthe reverse image of the polar of a finite subset ofF1 contains the polar of a finite subset ofE1, if and only iff1maps finite subsets ofF1to finite subsets ofE1. Asf mapspEw1 q1topFw1q1we have then by the same reasoning thatf1is weakly* continuous.

In particular, any continuous linear mapf is weakly continuous, and thus has a transposef1 : F1 //E1. The converse however is not always true: a function can be weakly continuous but not continuous, asFmight contains 0-neighborhoods which are not polars of finite subsets ofF1. The previous proposition generalizes to:

Proposition 3.5.16. Consider a linear mapf :E //FandBandCbornologies onEandFrespectively. Then f1:FC1 //EB1 is continuous if and only if for anyBPBfpBq˝˝PC.

Let us state very clearly the following easy proposition, which is fundamental throughout this thesis. It could also be deduced from Proposition4.0.10, as reflexive spaces are barreled and thus endowed with their Mackey topology.

Proposition 3.5.17. ConsiderEandFstrongly reflexive spaces. Then we have a linear homeomorphismLβpEβ1, Fq » LβpFβ1, Eq.

Proof. Considerf PLpEβ1, Fq. Asfis continuous, it is weakly continuous, thusf1:Fβ1 //pEβ1q1βis continuous.

Asfis continuous and therefore bounded, it sends bounded sets to bounded sets, and thusf1is continuous. AsEis reflexive,f1is continuous fromFβ1 //E. The mappingf ÞÑf1is continuous: indeed, considerBFan absolutely convex and weakly closed bounded set inF andBEa bounded set inE. Iff1pBF˝

q ĎBE˝˝, thenfpBE˝

q ĎBF˝˝

. The situation being completely symmetrical, we have that forgPLpFβ1, Eq, we haveg1PLpEβ1, Fq, andgÞÑg1 is continuous.

Dans le document manuscript (Page 79-83)