• Aucun résultat trouvé

Lived body / lived world: phenomenological approach

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "Lived body / lived world: phenomenological approach"

Copied!
3
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-00980516

https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00980516

Submitted on 18 Apr 2014

HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers.

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés.

Lived body / lived world: phenomenological approach

Armen Khatchatourov, John Stewart

To cite this version:

Armen Khatchatourov, John Stewart. Lived body / lived world: phenomenological approach. En- action and enactive interfaces : a handbook of terms, Enactive Systems Books, pp.183-185, 2007.

�hal-00980516�

(2)

Enaction and Enactive Interfaces: A Handbook of Terms 3

7'*+)!3()8!9!:'*+)!;(-:)0!

<=+#(6+#(:(>'%$:!$<<-($%=!

Armen Khatchatourov [COSTECH]

John Stewart [COSTECH]

Lived world is a term of central import- ance for understanding human action, includ- ing the case of (computer) mediated action.

Lived world is a rather clumsy English rendering of the German Umwelt. The term is used by Husserl (and in phenomenology in general; see Merleau-Ponty and the French

monde propre) to designate the world as it

exists from the point of view of the perceiv- ing subject, after the exercise of phenomeno- logical reduction. What is enacted or brought forth by a human subject is a world of lived experience, world as a world of possibilities, of things and situations which makes sense for the subject, and not the objective and neutral world as-it-is.

The term was also employed by the Ger- man ethologist von Uexküll to designate the world as experienced by this or that species of animal. A famous example is the world of the tick. Even though it is blind, deaf and dumb (and can only crawl slowly), the tick nevertheless succeeds in the remarkable feat of identifying a warm-blooded mammal, catching it and feeding by sucking its blood.

To do this, tick uses just 3 bits of informa- tion, which von Uexküll identified experi- mentally in a laboratory setting:

-

Butyric acid / or not. If there is, the tick lets itself fall from its perch on the twig of a bush.

-

Hairy / smooth surface. If the surface is hairy, the tick crawls until it finds a smooth surface i.e. bare skin; it then pierces the surface with its head.

-

Liquid at 37+2°C / or not. If yes, the tick will suck the liquid.

The concatenation of these three percep- tion-action cycles, in ecological context,

enables the tick to find a mammal. The lived world of the tick is thus remarkably impover- ished, containing just three beacons; but this minimalist simplicity conditions robustness of the actions, and robustness is more im- portant than richness.

It is interesting to note that the Gestalt psychologists (largely inspired by phenomen- ology) made a similar effort to avoid the error of the stimulus – the error in question consisting of attributing perceptual experi- ence to the perceived objects, to the detri- ment of describing the actual subjective experience as such.

There is a similar distinction between body and lived body: on the one hand, the biologi- cal body as a physical object (Körper), on the other hand the lived body as the seat of subjective experience (lived body is a rather clumsy English rendering of the German

Leib, French corps propre or chair). The inter-

play between these two radically inseparable facets of the body leads to the theme of embodiment.

Let us consider the situation called tactile chiasmus, when one explores by touch his left hand with his right hand. In that case, the subject feels his left hand from the inside, as being touched. However, at the same time, for the right hand, the left hand is also an object of the world, that is considered as any other object. The notion of lived body is closely related to the kinaesthesia, under- stood as the very locus of inhabiting the body and feeling it from the inside.

Finally these notions should be under- stood, strictly speaking, in the light of the specific phenomenological methodology which is called phenomenological reduction.

The basic method is that of phenomenologi-

cal reduction or

Epokhè. Phenomenological

reduction consists in putting into parentheses

the naïve thesis of the existence of the exter-

nal world; and in neutralizing belief in the

existence (or indeed the non-existence) of

objects in the world. This is methodologically

necessary in order to focus attention on the

mode of appearance of objects, and hence to

(3)

4 Enaction and Enactive Interfaces: A Handbook of Terms

define the way objects appear to the con- sciousness (or the modalities of their coming into presence). It is important not to confuse phenomenological reduction with introspec- tion, with a restriction or limitation, nor with reductionism as it is be practised in the con- text of scientific enquiry.

Phenomenological reduction leads to the discovery of the intentional structure of consciousness. While maintaining the Kant- ian insistence on the transcendental level, Husserl put emphasis on the concept of phenomenon (i.e. what appears to the con- sciousness, and the way it appears to the consciousness, and this independently from the real existence of the object). He then redefines consciousness in terms of inten- tionality. Consciousness is no longer a think- ing substance (res cogitans), but rather a dynamic action whereby (the subject) aims at (something).

Phenomenology thus introduces a double shift from classical approaches to the ques- tion of knowledge:

-

On the one hand, phenomenology seeks to account not for the object that appears to the consciousness, but for the way in which the object appears. This process of appearing supposes that there is an a priori correlation between consciousness and its objects; experience – and hence knowledge – only exists for (a subject of conscious- ness); conversely, consciousness is always consciousness of (something).

-

On the other hand, contrary to Kant for whom the a priori categories of experience (space and time) are purely formal catego- ries, phenomenology seeks to describe up to the cognitive categories as arising from the flow of the lived experience. These ideas, though related to the transcendental tradition, renews it radically; the notion of lived experience (Erlebnis), which is the centre of gravity of phenomenology, im- plies that knowledge and consciousness is not possible without a grounding in em- bodiment.

Through this thematisation of lived body and embodiment, phenomenology leads thus to a reconceptualization of consciousness, which is then understood as an activity of the subject which enacts the lived world. Al- though the concept of enaction was intro- duced by Varela and Maturana, it is largely inspired by – and grounded on - phenomen- ology.

?+:$&+)!'&+6/!

!"#$%&'&(")'*+$','-(.#+

!")/&,%0&(1(/#+

2)'0&(13+0".)(&(13+/0(3)03/4+567+

8309)(0'*+',&3:'0&/+')-+$3,03$&%'*+3;$3,(3)03+

8"%09<+&93+/3)/3+":+,3'*(&=+

Références

Documents relatifs

Key words: body force, elastic body, Fourier transform, ill − posed problem, Tikhonov’s regularization, truncated integration.. We shall assume that the boundary of the elastic body

(1) if K is acute, ♥(K) is contained in the triangle formed by the segments joining the midpoints of the sides of K; also, ♥(K) equals the quadrangle Q formed by the bisectors of

Finally, he was able to avoid the vexing issue of ‘popular’ religion and its nagging oppositions between rich/poor, emotional/rational,

While recognizing the interest of the type of anthropology which allows – for example - the doctor to consider a patient’s body as an object of analysis independent of her own

Tâche : Résume ce que dit le texte (que tu as trouvé en anglais) concernant les 5 sujets ci- dessous, cela te permettra de poursuivre tes échanges avec Kirsten en ayant une meilleure

Thus, proprioceptive consciousness would be similar to peripheral visual perception (Kinsbourne, 1995): visual information at the periphery of the retina is less

These few examples from a much larger body of research indicate that high levels of distress due to life crises, the Type A behaviour pattern, and hostility are

The mere fact that issues pertaining to this field are brought before the courts points to a growing trend towards the “juridicisation” of privacy (or