• Aucun résultat trouvé

Using linear logic and proof theory to unify computational logic

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "Using linear logic and proof theory to unify computational logic"

Copied!
3
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-01615673

https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01615673

Submitted on 13 Oct 2017

HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers.

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés.

Using linear logic and proof theory to unify computational logic

Dale Miller

To cite this version:

Dale Miller. Using linear logic and proof theory to unify computational logic. Proceedings of Trends in Linear Logic and Applications (TLLA 17), Sep 2017, Oxford, United Kingdom. �hal-01615673�

(2)

Using linear logic and proof theory to unify computational logic

by Dale Miller, Inria To be presented at

TLLA 17: Trends in Linear Logic and Applications 3 September 2017, Oxford, UK

The opening sentence of Girard’s 1987 paper introducing linear logic contains the words “Linear logic is a logic behind logic”. In this talk, I will explore a slight variation of this phrase: “Linear logic is the logic behind computational logic”. Switching the indefinite article into a definite article is, of course, dangerous since we do not know what future analysis might reveal. I retain this switch here since, for the scope of this talk, I will not be tempted to consider any alternative to the core principles of linear logic.

Also, this latter phrase narrows “logic” to just “computational logic”. By this term, I mean, the discipline that has evolved within theoretical computer science for which there are now several conferences (such as LICS and CSL) as well as journals (such as theTransactions on Computational Logic). In particular, I assume that computational logic includes the following topics:

• Logic programming (proof search)

• Term representation

• Type systems (Curry-Howard)

• Functional programming (proof normalization)

• Model checking

• Theorem proving in logic and arithmetic, both automatic and interac- tive.

Every one of these topics is mature (having been studied now for decades) and broadly applicable (having numerous applications in practice or within computational logic itself). Every one of these topics is taught routinely to undergraduate or graduate students interested in applying formal methods to computer science problems.

Young people approaching topics in computational logic will find texts and articles that develop these topics in isolation from each other and with antipathy for one another. For example, intuitionistic logic was developed to rid (classical) logic of certain logical principles and model checking was

1

(3)

born in the 1980’s as an anti-proof movement (against Floyd-Hoare style proofs).

In this talk, I want to address the challenge of finding a core set of principles that could provide a foundation for all of these topics and, as such, allow students to understand principles that are common and to appreciate the different reasons those general principles need to be differentiated into these many, separate topics.

Our proposed common foundation includes the following three logics.

1. MALL, with its classification of connectives as being additive or mul- tiplicative and with having unambiguous polarities.

2. Linear logic (LL), as an extension of MALL with exponentials (and possibly with first-order and higher-order quantification). LL can serve as a foundation for classical and intuitionistic logics.

3. µMALL, as an extension of MALL with fixed points instead of ex- ponentials. This logic appears to be more appropriate than LL as a foundation for model checking and inductive (and coinductive) theo- rem proving.

The foundation of this development is built on the theory and structure of proofs (i.e., on proof theory). Here, sequent calculus is central. While many people feel that sequent calculus is just one choice of proof presen- tation (among other choices such as natural deduction, tableaux, Herbrand instances, dependently typed λ-terms, etc), I will promote the point that sequent calculus should be seen as having a distinguished position: it pro- vides the “assembly language” for realizing proof systems. The amorphous nature of Gentzen’s sequent calculus can be tamed and exploited by the use of focused proof systems. The notion of synthetic inference rules arising from focused proofs provides a framework that helps to link and distinguish the many topics within computational logic.

A corollary of our approach to organize computational logic is that top- ics such as model theory, category theory, type theory, algebra, and game semantics do not play a role in presenting a unified approach to computa- tional logic. Instead, those topics can be expected to provide deep results and historical connections in various specialized domains of computational logic.

Draft: 21 July 2017

2

Références

Documents relatifs

As a result of this unity, the sequent calculus provided logic programming a natural framework in which proof-search could be described for much richer logics (first-order

In the Kripke semantics defined for dual-intuitionistic logic (see [Gor00]), the dual of intuitionistic implication is interpreted as being valid in a possible world if it is valid

To summarize, our prescription for obtaining compact proof certificates is as follows: (1) start from a focused sequent proof; (2) uniquely name every subformula path in

The arbitrary assignment of positive (synchronous) and negative (asynchronous) bias to atomic formulas can have a major impact on, not the existence of focused proofs, but the shape

The missing piece to decompose cuts to their atomic form as shown in (9) is the rule s↑, dual to the switch s↓ rule, which allows to move a substructure in positive position outside

Classical logic focuses on truth (hence truth values) Intuitionistic logic focuses on provability (hence proofs) A is true if it is provable. The excluded

Since it has been understood that the Curry-Howard isomorphism relating proofs and programs can be extended to classical logic, various systems have been introduced: the λ c

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des