• Aucun résultat trouvé

Axiomatization and Implementation of a Class of Solidarity Values

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Partager "Axiomatization and Implementation of a Class of Solidarity Values"

Copied!
56
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

Class of Solidarity Values

Sylvain Béal

1

, Eric Rémila

2

, Philippe Solal

2

1 CRESE, Université de Franche-Comté, France

2 GATE Lyon Saint-Etienne, Université de Saint-Etienne, France

November 2016

(2)

We introduce a (convex) class of values for TU-games which combine marginalist and egalitarian principles.

This class of values belongs to the class of Efficient, Anonymous and Linear values characterized by Ruiz et al.

(1998) and Radzik and Driessen (2013), among others.

We remark that this class of values constitutes in fact a subclass of the Procedural values (Malawski, 2013), and contains the Egalitarian Shapley values (Joosten, 1996) and the Solidarity value (Novak and Radzik 1994), but excludes the

δ-Shapley values

(Joosten, 1996) and the Consensus value (Ju et al., 2007).

We provide a characterization of this class of values in terms

of the coefficients given by Radzik and Driessen (2013) to

express the

Efficient,Anonymous

and

Linear

values via the

Shapley value (1953).

(3)

We introduce a (convex) class of values for TU-games which combine marginalist and egalitarian principles.

This class of values belongs to the class of Efficient, Anonymous and Linear values characterized by Ruiz et al.

(1998) and Radzik and Driessen (2013), among others.

We remark that this class of values constitutes in fact a subclass of the Procedural values (Malawski, 2013), and contains the Egalitarian Shapley values (Joosten, 1996) and the Solidarity value (Novak and Radzik 1994), but excludes the

δ-Shapley values

(Joosten, 1996) and the Consensus value (Ju et al., 2007).

We provide a characterization of this class of values in terms

of the coefficients given by Radzik and Driessen (2013) to

express the Efficient, Anonymous and Linear values via the

Shapley value (1953).

(4)

We introduce a (convex) class of values for TU-games which combine marginalist and egalitarian principles.

This class of values belongs to the class of Efficient, Anonymous and Linear values characterized by Ruiz et al.

(1998) and Radzik and Driessen (2013), among others.

We remark that this class of values constitutes in fact a subclass of the Procedural values (Malawski, 2013), and contains the Egalitarian Shapley values (Joosten, 1996) and the Solidarity value (Novak and Radzik 1994), but excludes the

δ-Shapley values

(Joosten, 1996) and the Consensus value (Ju et al., 2007).

We provide a characterization of this class of values in terms

of the coefficients given by Radzik and Driessen (2013) to

express the Efficient, Anonymous and Linear values via the

Shapley value (1953).

(5)

We introduce a (convex) class of values for TU-games which combine marginalist and egalitarian principles.

This class of values belongs to the class of Efficient, Anonymous and Linear values characterized by Ruiz et al.

(1998) and Radzik and Driessen (2013), among others.

We remark that this class of values constitutes in fact a subclass of the Procedural values (Malawski, 2013), and contains the Egalitarian Shapley values (Joosten, 1996) and the Solidarity value (Novak and Radzik 1994), but excludes the

δ-Shapley values

(Joosten, 1996) and the Consensus value (Ju et al., 2007).

We provide a characterization of this class of values in terms

of the coefficients given by Radzik and Driessen (2013) to

express the Efficient, Anonymous and Linear values via the

Shapley value (1953).

(6)

We provide an axiomatic characterization of the extreme points of this class of values.

We also provide an axiomatic characterization of the full class of values, which is comparable to both the characterization of the Procedural values (Malawski) and the characterization of the Egalitarian Shapley values provided by Casajus and Huettner (2013).

Finally, we provide a strategic foundation of these values by

designing a class of bidding mechanisms which implement

them in subgame Nash perfect equilibrium.

(7)

We provide an axiomatic characterization of the extreme points of this class of values.

We also provide an axiomatic characterization of the full class of values, which is comparable to both the characterization of the Procedural values (Malawski) and the characterization of the Egalitarian Shapley values provided by Casajus and Huettner (2013).

Finally, we provide a strategic foundation of these values by

designing a class of bidding mechanisms which implement

them in subgame Nash perfect equilibrium.

(8)

We provide an axiomatic characterization of the extreme points of this class of values.

We also provide an axiomatic characterization of the full class of values, which is comparable to both the characterization of the Procedural values (Malawski) and the characterization of the Egalitarian Shapley values provided by Casajus and Huettner (2013).

Finally, we provide a strategic foundation of these values by

designing a class of bidding mechanisms which implement

them in subgame Nash perfect equilibrium.

(9)

The set N represents a fixed and finite set of agents of size n.

A coalition function on N is a function v : 2

N

−→

R

which assigns a worth v(S) ∈

R

to each coalition S ∈ 2

N

, and where v(∅) = 0;

A TU-game v is monotone if S ⊇ T implies v(S) ≥ v(T ); and positive if, for each S ∈ 2

N

, v(S) ≥ 0.

Let V

N

be the set of such coalition functions or TU-games v

on N . A value on V

N

is a function Φ : V

N

−→

Rn

which

assigns a payoff vector Φ(v) ∈

Rn

to each v ∈ V

N

.

(10)

The Egalitarian Division rule, ED, is defined on V

N

as:

∀i ∈ N, ED

i

(v) = v(N ) n .

For any permutation σ on N and any agent i ∈ N , consider the coalition containing i and the set of his/her predecessors in σ as P

iσ

= {j ∈ N : σ(j) ≤ σ(i)}. The Shapley value, Sh, is defined on V

N

as follows:

∀i ∈ N, Sh

i

(v) = 1 n!

X

σ∈ΣN

v(P

iσ

) − v(P

iσ

\ i)

=

X

S∈2N:S3i

(n − s)!(s − 1)!

n! v(S) − v(S \ i)

.

(11)

Some values which incorporate a solidarity principle in two different ways.

The Egalitarian Shapley values are the convex combinations of the Shapley values and the Egalitarian values:

∃α ∈ [0, 1] : ∀i ∈ N, EDSh

αi

(v) = αSh

i

(v) + (1 − α)ED

i

(v).

The Solidarity value (Nowak and Radzik, 1993), which takes into account the average marginal contribution of all members of a coalition:

∀i ∈ N, NR

i

(v) =

X

S∈2N:S3i

(n − s)!(s − 1)!

n!

X

j∈S

v(S) − v(S \ j) s

.

(12)

All the above-mentioned values belongs to the class of values on V

N

which are Efficient, Anonymous and Linear, and denoted by EAL

N

.

Proposition

(Radzik and Driessen, 2013)

A value Φ on V

N

belongs to

EALN

if and only if there exists a unique vector of constants B

Φ

= (b

Φs

: s ∈ {0, 1, . . . , n}) such that b

Φ0

= 0, b

Φn

= 1, and

Φ(v) = Sh(B

Φ

v),

where (B

Φ

v)(S) = b

Φs

v(S) for each coalition S of size s,

s ∈ {0, 1, . . . , n},

(13)

b Sh

s

= 1;

b ED

s

= 0;

b EDSh

α

s

= α;

b NR

s

= 1

s + 1 .

(14)

Malawski (2013) introduces the subclass PV

N

EAL

N

of Procedural values which incorporate a solidarity principle among the agents.

A procedure specifies how the (marginal) contribution of each agent is shared with his or her predecessors in each ordering σ of the agent set.

Formally, a procedure

`

on N is a collection of nonnegative coefficients

((`p,q)pq=1)np=1

s.t. for each p

∈ {1, . . . , n}, Pp

q=1`p,q= 1. The coefficient

`

p,q

specifies the share of agent at position q

p in the marginal contribution of agent at position p in the ordering:

∀i∈

N, r

iσ,`(v) = X

j∈N:σ(j)≥σ(i)

`

σ(j),σ(i)

v(P

jσ)−

v(P

jσ\

j)

.

(15)

Malawski (2013) introduces the subclass PV

N

EAL

N

of Procedural values which incorporate a solidarity principle among the agents.

A procedure specifies how the (marginal) contribution of each agent is shared with his or her predecessors in each ordering σ of the agent set.

Formally, a procedure

`

on N is a collection of nonnegative coefficients

((`p,q)pq=1)np=1

s.t. for each p

∈ {1, . . . , n}, Pp

q=1`p,q= 1. The coefficient

`

p,q

specifies the share of agent at position q

p in the marginal contribution of agent at position p in the ordering:

∀i∈

N, r

iσ,`(v) = X

j∈N:σ(j)≥σ(i)

`

σ(j),σ(i)

v(P

jσ)−

v(P

jσ\

j)

.

(16)

Malawski (2013) introduces the subclass PV

N

EAL

N

of Procedural values which incorporate a solidarity principle among the agents.

A procedure specifies how the (marginal) contribution of each agent is shared with his or her predecessors in each ordering σ of the agent set.

Formally, a procedure

`

on N is a collection of nonnegative coefficients

((`p,q)pq=1)np=1

s.t. for each p ∈ {1, . . . , n},

Pp

q=1`p,q= 1. The coefficient

`

p,q

specifies the share of agent at position q ≤ p in the marginal contribution of agent at position p in the ordering:

∀i ∈ N, r

iσ,`

(v) =

X

j∈N:σ(j)≥σ(i)

`

σ(j),σ(i)

v(P

jσ

) − v(P

jσ

\ j)

.

(17)

A Procedural value is defined as:

∀i ∈ N, Pv

`i

(v) = 1 n!

X

σ∈ΣN

r

iσ,`

(v).

Theorem 1 in Malawski (2013) shows that the allocation determined by a procedure ` depends only on the numbers

`

ss

, s

∈ {1, . . . , n}, where

`

11= 1.

Expressed in terms of the coefficients given by Radzik and Driessen (2013), a Procedural value induced by the procedure

` has the coefficients b

`s=

`

s+1,s+1

for s

∈ {1, . . . , n−1}

(Lemma 2 in Malawski, 2013).

In particular, we have:

EALN ⊃PvN ⊃EDShN ⊃ {Sh,ED}.

(18)

A Procedural value is defined as:

∀i ∈ N, Pv

`i

(v) = 1 n!

X

σ∈ΣN

r

iσ,`

(v).

Theorem 1 in Malawski (2013) shows that the allocation determined by a procedure ` depends only on the numbers

`

ss

, s ∈ {1, . . . , n}, where `

11

= 1.

Expressed in terms of the coefficients given by Radzik and Driessen (2013), a Procedural value induced by the procedure

` has the coefficients b

`s=

`

s+1,s+1

for s

∈ {1, . . . , n−1}

(Lemma 2 in Malawski, 2013).

In particular, we have:

EAL

N

Pv

N

EDSh

N ⊃ {Sh,

ED}.

(19)

A Procedural value is defined as:

∀i ∈ N, Pv

`i

(v) = 1 n!

X

σ∈ΣN

r

iσ,`

(v).

Theorem 1 in Malawski (2013) shows that the allocation determined by a procedure ` depends only on the numbers

`

ss

, s ∈ {1, . . . , n}, where `

11

= 1.

Expressed in terms of the coefficients given by Radzik and Driessen (2013), a Procedural value induced by the procedure

` has the coefficients b

`s

= `

s+1,s+1

for s ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}

(Lemma 2 in Malawski, 2013).

In particular, we have:

EAL

N

Pv

N

EDSh

N ⊃ {Sh,

ED}.

(20)

A Procedural value is defined as:

∀i ∈ N, Pv

`i

(v) = 1 n!

X

σ∈ΣN

r

iσ,`

(v).

Theorem 1 in Malawski (2013) shows that the allocation determined by a procedure ` depends only on the numbers

`

ss

, s ∈ {1, . . . , n}, where `

11

= 1.

Expressed in terms of the coefficients given by Radzik and Driessen (2013), a Procedural value induced by the procedure

` has the coefficients b

`s

= `

s+1,s+1

for s ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}

(Lemma 2 in Malawski, 2013).

In particular, we have:

EAL

N

Pv

N

EDSh

N ⊃ {Sh,

ED}.

(21)

We introduce a set of solidarity values, denoted by Sol

N

, which rely on both marginalist and egalitarian principles. The scenario envisaged to define and compute these values consists of the following steps:

1

Consider any integer p between 0 and n − 1;

2

Choose any v

V

N

and any σ

∈ΣN

in order to gradually form the grand coalition N ;

3

Each agent i

N arriving at position

σ(i)≤p

obtains his contribution c

σ,pi (v) =

v(P

iσ)−

v(P

iσ\

i) upon entering;

4

Each agent

i∈N

arriving at position

σ(i)> p

obtains an equal share of the remaining worth

v(N)−v(Pσσ−1(p)), i.e.

cσ,pi =

v(N)−v(Pσσ−1(p)) n−p .

(22)

We introduce a set of solidarity values, denoted by Sol

N

, which rely on both marginalist and egalitarian principles. The scenario envisaged to define and compute these values consists of the following steps:

1

Consider any integer p between 0 and n − 1;

2

Choose any v ∈ V

N

and any σ ∈ Σ

N

in order to gradually form the grand coalition N ;

3

Each agent i

N arriving at position

σ(i)≤p

obtains his contribution c

σ,pi (v) =

v(P

iσ)−

v(P

iσ\

i) upon entering;

4

Each agent i

N arriving at position

σ(i)> p

obtains an equal share of the remaining worth v(N

)−

v(P

σσ−1(p)), i.e.

c

σ,pi =

v(N

)−

v(P

σσ−1(p))

n

p .

(23)

We introduce a set of solidarity values, denoted by Sol

N

, which rely on both marginalist and egalitarian principles. The scenario envisaged to define and compute these values consists of the following steps:

1

Consider any integer p between 0 and n − 1;

2

Choose any v ∈ V

N

and any σ ∈ Σ

N

in order to gradually form the grand coalition N ;

3

Each agent i ∈ N arriving at position

σ(i)≤p

obtains his contribution c

σ,pi

(v) = v(P

iσ

) − v(P

iσ

\ i) upon entering;

4

Each agent i

N arriving at position

σ(i)> p

obtains an equal share of the remaining worth v(N

)−

v(P

σσ−1(p)), i.e.

c

σ,pi =

v(N

)−

v(P

σσ−1(p))

n

p .

(24)

We introduce a set of solidarity values, denoted by Sol

N

, which rely on both marginalist and egalitarian principles. The scenario envisaged to define and compute these values consists of the following steps:

1

Consider any integer p between 0 and n − 1;

2

Choose any v ∈ V

N

and any σ ∈ Σ

N

in order to gradually form the grand coalition N ;

3

Each agent i ∈ N arriving at position

σ(i)≤p

obtains his contribution c

σ,pi

(v) = v(P

iσ

) − v(P

iσ

\ i) upon entering;

4

Each agent i ∈ N arriving at position

σ(i)> p

obtains an equal share of the remaining worth v(N ) − v(P

σσ−1(p)

), i.e.

c

σ,pi

=

v(N ) − v(P

σσ−1(p)

)

n − p .

(25)

5

Steps 1-4 determine a payoff vector denoted by

cσ,p(v)

Rn

;

6

Define the payoff vector Sol

p(v)

as the average of the payoff vectors c

σ,p(v)

over the n! orderings σ

∈ΣN

;

7

Assume p is drawn according to the probability distribution

α= (αp :p∈ {0, . . . , n−1}). The

Solidarity value w.r.t. α is defined as the expected payoff vector Sol

α(v)

given by:

Sol

α(v) =

n−1

X

p=0

α

p

Sol

p(v).

For each i

N , Sol

pi(v)

can also be expressed as:

Sol

pi(v) = X

S3i,s≤p

(n−

s)!(s

−1)!

n! v(S)

v(S

\

i)

+ X

S63i,s=p

(n−

s

−1)!s!

n! v(N

)−

v(S)

.

(26)

5

Steps 1-4 determine a payoff vector denoted by

cσ,p(v)

Rn

;

6

Define the payoff vector Sol

p(v)

as the average of the payoff vectors c

σ,p

(v) over the n! orderings σ ∈ Σ

N

;

7

Assume p is drawn according to the probability distribution

α= (αp :p∈ {0, . . . , n−1}). The

Solidarity value w.r.t. α is defined as the expected payoff vector Sol

α(v)

given by:

Sol

α(v) =

n−1

X

p=0

α

p

Sol

p(v).

For each i

N , Sol

pi(v)

can also be expressed as:

Sol

pi(v) = X

S3i,s≤p

(n−

s)!(s

−1)!

n! v(S)

v(S

\

i)

+ X

S63i,s=p

(n−

s

−1)!s!

n! v(N

)−

v(S)

.

(27)

5

Steps 1-4 determine a payoff vector denoted by

cσ,p(v)

Rn

;

6

Define the payoff vector Sol

p(v)

as the average of the payoff vectors c

σ,p

(v) over the n! orderings σ ∈ Σ

N

;

7

Assume p is drawn according to the probability distribution

α= (αp :p∈ {0, . . . , n−1}). The

Solidarity value w.r.t. α is defined as the expected payoff vector Sol

α(v)

given by:

Sol

α

(v) =

n−1

X

p=0

α

p

Sol

p

(v).

For each i ∈ N , Sol

pi

(v) can also be expressed as:

Sol

pi

(v) =

X

S3i,s≤p

(n − s)!(s − 1)!

n! v(S) − v(S \ i)

+

X

S63i,s=p

(n − s − 1)!s!

n! v(N ) − v(S)

.

(28)

To be more precise, each Sol

p

, p ∈ {0, . . . , n − 1}, an extreme point of the convex set of values

SolN

, has the following property:

Proposition

Fix any p ∈ {0, . . . , n − 1}.

1

If p = 0, then Sol

0

= ED; if p = n − 1, then Sol

n−1

= Sh.

2

For each v ∈ V

N

, Sol

p

(v) coincides with Sh(B

p

v), where B

p

= (b

ps

: s ∈ {0, 1, . . . , n}) is such that:

b

p0

= 0, b

pn

= 1, b

ps

=

1 if s ∈ {1, . . . , p},

0 if s ∈ {p + 1, . . . , n − 1}.

(29)

From the above property, we obtain a characterization of Sol

N

using the representation of values in EAL

N

provided by Radzik and Driessen (2013).

Proposition

A value

Φ

on V

N

belongs to

SolN

if and only it can be represented by the Shapley value applied to TU-games B

Φ

v with constants B

Φ= (bΦs :

s

∈ {0, . . . , n})

such that:

b

Φ0 = 0, bΦn = 1,

and

∀s∈ {1, . . . , n−1}, 1≥

b

Φ1

b

Φ2 ≥ · · · ≥

b

Φn−1 ≥0.

Furthermore,

Φ =

Sol

α

where α

= (αs:

s

∈ {0, . . . , n−1})

is obtained from the transformation B

Φ7−→

α such that:

α

0 = 1−bΦ1

, α

n−1=

b

Φn−1

, and

∀s∈ {1, . . . , n−2}, αs=

b

Φs−bΦs+1

.

(30)

From the above property, we obtain a characterization of Sol

N

using the representation of values in EAL

N

provided by Radzik and Driessen (2013).

Proposition

A value Φ on V

N

belongs to

SolN

if and only it can be represented by the Shapley value applied to TU-games B

Φ

v with constants B

Φ

= (b

Φs

: s ∈ {0, . . . , n}) such that:

b

Φ0

= 0, b

Φn

= 1, and

∀s ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}, 1 ≥ b

Φ1

≥ b

Φ2

≥ · · · ≥ b

Φn−1

≥ 0.

Furthermore, Φ = Sol

α

where α = (α

s

: s ∈ {0, . . . , n − 1}) is obtained from the transformation B

Φ

7−→ α such that:

α

0

= 1−b

Φ1

, α

n−1

= b

Φn−1

, and ∀s ∈ {1, . . . , n−2}, α

s

= b

Φs

−b

Φs+1

.

(31)

The next result shows that Sol

N

⊂ Pv

N

.

Proposition

For each probability distribution α, Sol

α

= Pv

`α

, where `

α

is defined as:

`

αk,q

=









α

q−1

if q < k,

n−1

X

j=k−1

α

j

if q = k.

The contribution of the agent entering at position k is shared

as follows: for q < k, the agent entering at position q receives

a share α

q−1

of the contribution, and the agent k keeps the

remaining part.

(32)

The next result shows that Sol

N

⊂ Pv

N

.

Proposition

For each probability distribution α, Sol

α

= Pv

`α

, where `

α

is defined as:

`

αk,q

=









α

q−1

if q < k,

n−1

X

j=k−1

α

j

if q = k.

The contribution of the agent entering at position k is shared

as follows: for q < k, the agent entering at position q receives

a share α

q−1

of the contribution, and the agent k keeps the

remaining part.

(33)

Conclusion: It holds that

EAL

N

⊃ Pv

N

⊃ Sol

N

⊃ EDSh

N

⊃ {Sh, ED}.

(34)

We first introduce a variant of the null agent axiom in order to characterize Sol

p

, p ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}. Modifications of the axiom of null agent are numerous in the literature, see e.g.

Nowak and Radzik (1994), Ju et al. (2007), Kamijo and Kongo (2012), Chameni Nembua (2012), Casajus and Huettner (2014), Béal et al. (2015), van den Brink and Funaki (2015), and Radzik and Driessen (2016).

Given p

∈ {1, . . . , n−1}, and

v

V

N

, we say that i

N is a

p-null agent

in v if:

∀S 3

i, s

p, v(S) = v(S\i) and

∀S 63

i, s

=

p, v(N

) =

v(S).

Remark: in case p

=

n

−1,

p-null agent coincides with null agent.

(35)

We first introduce a variant of the null agent axiom in order to characterize Sol

p

, p ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}. Modifications of the axiom of null agent are numerous in the literature, see e.g.

Nowak and Radzik (1994), Ju et al. (2007), Kamijo and Kongo (2012), Chameni Nembua (2012), Casajus and Huettner (2014), Béal et al. (2015), van den Brink and Funaki (2015), and Radzik and Driessen (2016).

Given p ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}, and v ∈ V

N

, we say that i ∈ N is a

p-null agent

in v if:

∀S 3 i, s ≤ p, v(S) = v(S\i) and ∀S 63 i, s = p, v(N ) = v(S).

Remark: in case p

=

n

−1,

p-null agent coincides with null agent.

(36)

We first introduce a variant of the null agent axiom in order to characterize Sol

p

, p ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}. Modifications of the axiom of null agent are numerous in the literature, see e.g.

Nowak and Radzik (1994), Ju et al. (2007), Kamijo and Kongo (2012), Chameni Nembua (2012), Casajus and Huettner (2014), Béal et al. (2015), van den Brink and Funaki (2015), and Radzik and Driessen (2016).

Given p ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}, and v ∈ V

N

, we say that i ∈ N is a

p-null agent

in v if:

∀S 3 i, s ≤ p, v(S) = v(S\i) and ∀S 63 i, s = p, v(N ) = v(S).

Remark: in case p = n − 1, p-null agent coincides with null agent.

(37)

p-null agent axiom

A value Φ on V

N

satisfies the p-null player axiom if, for each v ∈ V

N

and each p-null agent i ∈ N in v, it holds that: Φ

i

(v) = 0.

Proposition

A value

Φ

on V

N

is equal to Sol

p

, p

∈ {1, . . . , n−1}, if and only if

it satisfies Efficiency, Equal treatment of equals, Additivity, and

the p-null agent axiom.

(38)

p-null agent axiom

A value Φ on V

N

satisfies the p-null player axiom if, for each v ∈ V

N

and each p-null agent i ∈ N in v, it holds that: Φ

i

(v) = 0.

Proposition

A value Φ on V

N

is equal to Sol

p

, p ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}, if and only if

it satisfies Efficiency, Equal treatment of equals, Additivity, and

the p-null agent axiom.

(39)

A value Φ on V

N

satisfies:

Desirability if for each v ∈ V

N

and each pair {i, j} ⊆ N such that, for each S ⊆ N \ {i, j}, v(S ∪ i) ≥ v(S ∪ j), it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≥ Φ

j

(v);

Monotonicity if for each monotone v

V

N

and each i

N , it holds that:

Φi(v)≥0;

Null agent in a productive environment if for each v

V

N

such that v(N

)≥0, and each null agent

i

N in v, it holds that:

Φi(v)≥0;

Null agent in a null environment for positive games

if for each

positive

v∈VN

such that

v(N) = 0

and each null agent

i∈N

in

v, it holds that: Φi(v)≤0.

(40)

A value Φ on V

N

satisfies:

Desirability if for each v ∈ V

N

and each pair {i, j} ⊆ N such that, for each S ⊆ N \ {i, j}, v(S ∪ i) ≥ v(S ∪ j), it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≥ Φ

j

(v);

Monotonicity if for each monotone v ∈ V

N

and each i ∈ N , it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≥ 0;

Null agent in a productive environment if for each v

V

N

such that v(N

)≥0, and each null agent

i

N in v, it holds that:

Φi(v)≥0;

Null agent in a null environment for positive games if for each

positive v

V

N

such that v(N

) = 0

and each null agent i

N

in v, it holds that:

Φi(v)≤0.

(41)

A value Φ on V

N

satisfies:

Desirability if for each v ∈ V

N

and each pair {i, j} ⊆ N such that, for each S ⊆ N \ {i, j}, v(S ∪ i) ≥ v(S ∪ j), it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≥ Φ

j

(v);

Monotonicity if for each monotone v ∈ V

N

and each i ∈ N , it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≥ 0;

Null agent in a productive environment if for each v ∈ V

N

such that v(N ) ≥ 0, and each null agent i ∈ N in v, it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≥ 0;

Null agent in a null environment for positive games if for each

positive v

V

N

such that v(N

) = 0

and each null agent i

N

in v, it holds that:

Φi(v)≤0.

(42)

A value Φ on V

N

satisfies:

Desirability if for each v ∈ V

N

and each pair {i, j} ⊆ N such that, for each S ⊆ N \ {i, j}, v(S ∪ i) ≥ v(S ∪ j), it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≥ Φ

j

(v);

Monotonicity if for each monotone v ∈ V

N

and each i ∈ N , it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≥ 0;

Null agent in a productive environment if for each v ∈ V

N

such that v(N ) ≥ 0, and each null agent i ∈ N in v, it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≥ 0;

Null agent in a null environment for positive games if for each

positive v ∈ V

N

such that v(N ) = 0 and each null agent i ∈ N

in v, it holds that: Φ

i

(v) ≤ 0.

(43)

Proposition

(Malawski, 2013)

A value Φ on V

N

belongs to

PvN

if and only if it satisfies Efficiency, Desirability, Additivity, and Monotonicity.

Proposition

(Casajus and Huettner, 2013)

A value

Φ

on V

N

belongs to

EDShN

if and only if it satisfies

Efficiency, Desirability, Additivity, and the Null agent axiom in a

productive environment.

(44)

Proposition

(Malawski, 2013)

A value Φ on V

N

belongs to

PvN

if and only if it satisfies Efficiency, Desirability, Additivity, and Monotonicity.

Proposition

(Casajus and Huettner, 2013)

A value Φ on V

N

belongs to

EDShN

if and only if it satisfies

Efficiency, Desirability, Additivity, and the Null agent axiom in a

productive environment.

(45)

Proposition

A value Φ on V

N

belongs to

SolN

if and only if it satisfies

Efficiency, Additivity, Desirability, Monotonicity, and Null agent in

a null environment for positive games.

(46)

We design a class of mechanisms which implement the values of Sol

N

in subgame perfect Nash equilibrium.

These mechanisms belong to the class of bidding mechanisms

initiated by Demange (1984) and Moulin (1984) for economic

environments and further adapted by Pérez-Castrillo and

Wettstein (2001) and Ju and Wettstein (2009) to implement

solution concepts for cooperative games.

(47)

Consider any TU-game v ∈ V

N

and any probability

distribution α = (α

p

)

n−1p=0

on {0, . . . , n − 1} and define A

α

as the support of α.

Mechanism (B)

Stage 1: each agent i ∈ N makes bids h

ip

R

, one for each position p ∈ A

α

, under the following constraint:

X

p∈Aα

α

p

h

ip

= 0.

For each position p ∈ A

α

, define the aggregate bid H

p

as:

H

p

=

X

i∈N

h

ip

.

Denote by Ω

Aα

the subset of positions with the highest aggregate

bid.

(48)

Stage 2: each agent i ∈ N makes bids h

iσ

R

, one for each ordering σ ∈ Σ

N

, under the constraint:

X

σ∈ΣN

1

n! h

iσ

= 0,

meaning that the designer values each ordering σ equally, i.e. for each σ ∈ Σ

N

, the weight α

σ

= 1/n!. For each σ ∈ Σ

N

, the

aggregate bid, defined in a similar way as in Stage 1, is denoted by

H

σ

. Finally, denote by Ω

ΣN

the subset of permutations with the

highest aggregate bid.

(49)

Stage 3: pick at random any p ∈ Ω

A

and then any σ ∈ Ω

ΣN

. Together, position p and ordering σ induce a sequential bargaining (sub)game

Gp,σ

whose payoffs are denoted by (g

p,σi

)

i∈N

. This bargaining game contains the following steps:

1

Agent i ∈ N in position σ(i) = p + 1 proposes an offer x

ij

R

to each other j ∈ N \ i.

2

The agents other than agent i, sequentially, either accept or reject the offer. If at least one agent rejects it, then the offer is rejected. Otherwise the offer is accepted.

3

If the offer is accepted, then the payoffs are given by:

g

p,σi =

v(N

)−P

j∈N\i

x

ij

, and

∀j∈

N

\

i, g

p,σj =

x

ij

.

4

If the offer is rejected, then each

j

in position

σ(j)≥p+ 1

leaves the bargaining procedure with a null payoff, i.e.

gp,σj = 0, while the agents j

in position

σ(j)≤p

proceed to

the next round to bargain over

v(Pσσ−1(p)).

(50)

Stage 3: pick at random any p ∈ Ω

A

and then any σ ∈ Ω

ΣN

. Together, position p and ordering σ induce a sequential bargaining (sub)game

Gp,σ

whose payoffs are denoted by (g

p,σi

)

i∈N

. This bargaining game contains the following steps:

1

Agent i ∈ N in position σ(i) = p + 1 proposes an offer x

ij

R

to each other j ∈ N \ i.

2

The agents other than agent i, sequentially, either accept or reject the offer. If at least one agent rejects it, then the offer is rejected. Otherwise the offer is accepted.

3

If the offer is accepted, then the payoffs are given by:

g

p,σi =

v(N

)−P

j∈N\i

x

ij

, and

∀j∈

N

\

i, g

p,σj =

x

ij

.

4

If the offer is rejected, then each j in position σ(j)

p

+ 1

leaves the bargaining procedure with a null payoff, i.e.

g

p,σj = 0, while the agents

j in position σ(j)

p proceed to

the next round to bargain over v(P

σσ−1(p)).

(51)

Stage 3: pick at random any p ∈ Ω

A

and then any σ ∈ Ω

ΣN

. Together, position p and ordering σ induce a sequential bargaining (sub)game

Gp,σ

whose payoffs are denoted by (g

p,σi

)

i∈N

. This bargaining game contains the following steps:

1

Agent i ∈ N in position σ(i) = p + 1 proposes an offer x

ij

R

to each other j ∈ N \ i.

2

The agents other than agent i, sequentially, either accept or reject the offer. If at least one agent rejects it, then the offer is rejected. Otherwise the offer is accepted.

3

If the offer is accepted, then the payoffs are given by:

g

p,σi

= v(N ) −

P

j∈N\i

x

ij

, and ∀j ∈ N \ i, g

p,σj

= x

ij

.

4

If the offer is rejected, then each j in position σ(j)

p

+ 1

leaves the bargaining procedure with a null payoff, i.e.

g

p,σj = 0, while the agents

j in position σ(j)

p proceed to

the next round to bargain over v(P

σσ−1(p)).

(52)

Stage 3: pick at random any p ∈ Ω

A

and then any σ ∈ Ω

ΣN

. Together, position p and ordering σ induce a sequential bargaining (sub)game

Gp,σ

whose payoffs are denoted by (g

p,σi

)

i∈N

. This bargaining game contains the following steps:

1

Agent i ∈ N in position σ(i) = p + 1 proposes an offer x

ij

R

to each other j ∈ N \ i.

2

The agents other than agent i, sequentially, either accept or reject the offer. If at least one agent rejects it, then the offer is rejected. Otherwise the offer is accepted.

3

If the offer is accepted, then the payoffs are given by:

g

p,σi

= v(N ) −

P

j∈N\i

x

ij

, and ∀j ∈ N \ i, g

p,σj

= x

ij

.

4

If the offer is rejected, then each j in position σ(j) ≥ p + 1 leaves the bargaining procedure with a null payoff, i.e.

g

p,σj

= 0, while the agents j in position σ(j) ≤ p proceed to

the next round to bargain over v(P

σσ−1(p)

).

(53)

5

The new proposer is agent i in position σ(i) = p. Agent i makes an offer x

ij

R

to each other j such that σ(j) < p. If the offer is unanimously accepted by all agents j in position σ(j) < p, then the payoffs are as follows:

g

p,σi

= v(P

iσ

) −

X

σ(j)<σ(i)

x

ij

and ∀j : σ(j) < σ(i), g

jp,σ

= x

ij

.

If the offer is rejected, then i in position σ(i) = p leaves the

bargaining procedure with a null payoff. Then, Step 5 is

repeated between the agents j in position σ(j) ≤ p − 1, where

the new proposer is agent in position p − 1. Step 5 is repeated

until a proposal is accepted. In case the bargaining procedure

reaches the situation where the only active agent i is such

that σ(i) = 1, then his or her payoff in G

p,σ

is equal to v(i).

(54)

G

p,σ

, are defined as:

∀i ∈ N, z

ip,σ

= g

ip,σ

− h

ip

− h

iσ

+ H

p

+ H

σ

n ,

i.e. each agent pays his or her bids, receives an equal share of the aggregate bids H(p) and H(σ) plus the payoff resulting from the bargaining procedure G

p,σ

. Finally, since p and σ are chosen randomly in Ω

Aα

and Ω

ΣN

, the expected payoff of each agent playing Mechanism (B) is given by:

∀i ∈ N, m

i

=

P

p∈Ω

P

σ∈ΩΣN

z

p,σi

|Ω

Aα

| × |Ω

ΣN

| .

(55)

At Stage 1 and Stage 2, the position p + 1 of the proposer and the ordering σ are chosen. At Stage 3, the bargaining

procedure is schematically as follows:

σ(1) · · · σ(p)

| {z }

σ(p + 1)

| {z }

σ(p + 2) · · · σ(n)

| {z }

Alternating offer proc. Proposer Take-it-or-leave-it proc.

A TU-game is zero-monotonic if its zero-normalization is a monotone TU-game.

Proposition

Consider any zero-monotonic TU-game v

V

N

and a probability distribution α with support A

α⊆ {0, . . . , n−1}. Then,

Mechanism (B) implements the Solidarity value Sol

α(v)

in

Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium.

(56)

At Stage 1 and Stage 2, the position p + 1 of the proposer and the ordering σ are chosen. At Stage 3, the bargaining

procedure is schematically as follows:

σ(1) · · · σ(p)

| {z }

σ(p + 1)

| {z }

σ(p + 2) · · · σ(n)

| {z }

Alternating offer proc. Proposer Take-it-or-leave-it proc.

A TU-game is zero-monotonic if its zero-normalization is a monotone TU-game.

Proposition

Consider any zero-monotonic TU-game v ∈ V

N

and a probability distribution α with support A

α

⊆ {0, . . . , n − 1}. Then,

Mechanism (B) implements the Solidarity value Sol

α

(v) in

Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium.

Références

Documents relatifs

Judith ce demande milles fois par jour ce qui pourrait ce passer si elle raconte tout, mais elle sait que en elle à besoin elle doit parler ….. Elle prends alors on telephone

This paper aims 1) to introduce the notion of theoretical story as a resource and source of constraint for the construction and assessment of models of phe- nomena; 2) to show

The &#34;no-values&#34; principie is a composite of tmpartiatuy (Principie 1) and autonomy scientific research (at least &#34;ba- sic&#34; research) is or should be dnven by

Il est indispensable de contrôler et de maitriser la phase pré analytique dans sa totalité pour ne pas avoir une modification qualitative ou quantitative du paramètre à doser,

Pendant les vacances, papa et maman travaillent alors nous allons passer les vacances chez nos grands-parents. Ils habitent à coté

These properties will be used throughout the text, as well as the fact that algebraic functions over Q(z) which are holomorphic at z = 0 are G-functions: this is a consequence

A considerable amount of literature about the concept of mean (or average) and the prop- erties of several means (such as the median, the arithmetic mean, the geometric mean, the

In this paper, we shall establish a rather general asymptotic formula in short intervals for a classe of arithmetic functions and announce two applications about the distribution