• Aucun résultat trouvé

Towards a Quantitative Theory of Variability

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "Towards a Quantitative Theory of Variability"

Copied!
11
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-00134205

https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00134205

Submitted on 1 Mar 2007

HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers.

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés.

Towards a Quantitative Theory of Variability

Philippe Blache

To cite this version:

Philippe Blache. Towards a Quantitative Theory of Variability: Language, brain and computation.

Ana-Maria Di Sciullo. UG and External Systems, John Benjamins, pp.375-388, 2005. �hal-00134205�

(2)

PhilippeBlache

LPL-CNRS, Universitede Provence

29,Avenue Robert Schuman

13621Aix-en-Provence, France

pb@lpl.univ-aix.fr

1 Introduction

Relations between dierent components of linguistic analysis, such as prosody, morphol-

ogy, syntax, semantics, discourse, etc. remains a problem for a systematic description (see

[Blache03]). However, thisis amainchallengenot onlyfrom a theoretical pointof view, but

also fornaturallanguageprocessing,especiallyinhuman/machinecommunicationsystemsor

speech processing (e.g. synthesis). Several phenomena highlighting such relations has been

described. This is typically the case for relations existing betweenprosody and syntax (see

[Selkirk84], [DiCristo85] or[Bear90]). However, explanations areoften empirical and excep-

tionally given intheperspectiveofanactualtheoryoflanguage. Itisforexamplepossibleto

specifysome relationsexisting between topicalization andsyllableduration (cf. [Doetjes02])

or between prosodic architecture and discourse organization after focus (cf. [DiCristo99]).

However, themodularityperspective, which relies on the independence of linguistic compo-

nents, remainstheruleinthiskindof descriptionand doesn't supporta globalvision ofthe

problem.

Oneof thediÆcultiesintheelaborationof ageneralaccount ofthisproblemcomesfrom

the fact that there are only few cases of superposition between structures of the dierent

components. ItisforexamplediÆculttoprecisesomecongruencepossibilitiesbetweensyntax

and prosody (see [Hirst98], [Mertens01]). In the same way, and these aspects are related,

the problem of variability is not taken into account in a systematic way for example inthe

framework of a theory. Indeed, we observe situations inwhich prosody can be realized in a

veryvariable waywhereasinsome other cases,strong constraintshave to be considered.

Wethinkthatthisquestionoftheinteractionbetweenthedierentlinguisticcomponents

isusuallyaddressedinthewrong(orincomplete)way. Itisimpossibletoexplainrelationsby

meansof abijectionsuperposingstructures(forexamplestipulatingdirectrelationsbetween

a syntactic tree and a prosodic hierarchy). One of the problems comes from the fact that

the linguistic objects are notthe same forsyntax and prosody: a word can be formedwith

several syllables,buta syllablecan in turnbeformedwithdierent words (cf. [Hirst98]).

Moregenerally,theproblemcomesfromtheconceptionoflinguisticinformationorganiza-

tion. It isdiÆcult(andprobablynotuseful)totry to representeach analysis component (1)

in anhomogeneous andhierarchized waybymeansof atotal relationand (2) independently

from other components. Inother words, we thinkthateach component of linguisticanalysis

isnotnecessarilyfullystructured: itisoftendiÆcult,orevenimpossible,tospecifyarelation

(3)

subordinationrelation.

il pleut tu es mouille(itrains you arewet) (1)

The sameobservationcan be doneforothercomponentsof linguisticanalysis. Thereare

for examplesome prosodicphenomena thataretypical andrecurrent inthisdomain(weuse

in this papera simpliedprosodic descriptionlimited to thenotion of contour presentedin

[Rossi99]), but it is not necessary to represent them into a hierarchized structure covering

the entire input. Generally speaking, each component participates in a partial manner to

the elaboration ofthe informationalcontent of anutterance. We arethen faraway fromthe

classicalmodularconceptionofanalysisconsistingindescribingthisprocessassequentialand

relyingonacompleteandsequentialanalysisofeachdomain(organizedinlevelanalysis,from

phoneticsto pragmatic). We think thattheinterpretation of anutterance is donethanksto

pieces of information comingfrom any component, eventuallyin a redundant way. There is

redundancy when congruence between components exists. But this is not the general case

in which part of informationcan come from prosody,another one from syntax,and another

from pragmatic, forexample.

We propose in this paper an approach taking advantage of this conception of linguistic

analysisandmakingitpossibletodescriberelationsbetweendierentcomponents,notatthe

structure level, but directly between objects belonging to dierent components involved in

therelation. Itbecomesthenpossibleto describerelationswithavariablegranularitylinking

objectsthatcanbeata dierentlevelfromone component totheother. Wecan forexample

describearelationbetweenaninterrogativemorphemeandanintonative contourorbetween

a phraseand some prosodicstress.

Such relations constitute a basis for describing and explaining variability. This phe-

nomenon cannotbeinterpretedby meansofdescriptions comingfrom aunique domain. We

propose an account of variability bringingtogether informationcoming from dierent com-

ponentsandstipulatinganequilibriumrelationbetweenthesecomponents. Theideaconsists

in indicating thatas soon asa certain quantityof information(aninformationthreshold) is

reached thanks to some linguistic components, then variability can appear in other compo-

nents. We willseeforexamplethat inthecasewheresyntaxcontainsinformationenoughby

itself, thenprosodybecomesvariable.

We propose to start from some examples illustrating some variability phenomena inthe

prosodicrealization. Wecanthenproviderstsomeconstraintspecifyingthisvariability. We

dene nallya principleprovidinga generalframework fordescribingvariability.

2 Some Examples

We present in thissection some examples together with a stylized intonative contour. This

kind ofrepresentation doesn'tallowto represent theset of prosodicphenomena that should

be taken into account for a precise study. It allows however a rst approximation in the

perspective of the question addressed in this paper. We use for this some of the notion

proposed in [Rossi99], in particular the notion of conclusive, parenthetic and continuative

(4)

ilpleut tuesmouille

itrains youarewet

This utterance is formed by twodistinct parts, not linked with

anyexplicit syntacticrelation. Intonation givesacorrelativein-

terpretationindicating\it rains, becauseyouare wet".

(2)

ilpleut tuesmouille

itrains youarewet

The same utterance, with a dierent intonation, receives a

causativeinterpretationindicating\ifitrains, thenyouarewet".

(3)

Marie larobe elleluivabien

Marie the dress ittohertswell

Example of a dislocation of two NPs with an

anaphoric relation with twoclitics. The intona-

tionfollowsthesamerisingschema foreach dis-

locatedNP.

(4)

Marie larobe elleluivabien

Marie the dress ittohertswell

Thesameexamplecanberealizedwithadierent

intonativecontour. Inbothcases,theinterpreta-

tionofadouble NP dislocationis favored,with-

outmanyambiguity(\thedresstsMary well") (5)

Marie lagarce elleluidonnerien

Marie the bitch shetohergives nothing

The syntactic structure is identical to

theone ofthepreviousexample. How-

ever,thepreferredinterpretationisthat

of an apposition morethan a multiple

dislocation. Thisinterpretationisrein-

forcedbyadierentintonativecontour

betweentheNPs,thesecondonebeing

parenthetic.

(6)

Marie lagarce elleluidonne rien

Marie thebitch shetohergives nothing

ThesameexampleseemsdiÆculttore-

alizewithanintonativecontourtypical

toadoubledislocation.

(7)

Marie elledevraitfaireattention

Marie sheshouldpayattention

Thesyntacticstructure correspondsto asimpledis-

location. TherisingcontouroftheNP constitutesa

strongprosodicmark.

(8)

Marie elledevraitfaireattention

Marie sheshouldpayattention

The form of this example is the sameas in the

previous example. However, the interpretation

isratheravocativeone,morethanadislocated.

Thisinterpretation isthendrivenbytheintona-

tion,notbythesyntacticstructure.

(9)

c'est la personne quim'interesse

itis the person that meinterests

The syntactic structure is that of a cleft. In this

realization,theintonationofthecleftNPismarked

withafall. Theinterpretationissomethinglike\itis

the personthat interests me(not theclothes) ".

(10)

(5)

c'est la personne quim'interesse

itis the person that meinterests

relative more than a cleft (of the kind \this is

her, eectively "). Itis drivenbytheintonation

that presentsacontinuativecontourratherthan

aconclusiveone.

(11)

c'est untruc qu'onprefere

itis atrick thatwe prefer

The interpretation of this example is that of a relative.

Suchinterpretationisnatural,withouttakingintoaccount

prosody(itisdiÆcultto associateacleftinterpretationto

this element which has apoorsemanticcontent). A typi-

cal cleft intonation(with a conclusivecontour) cannot be

easilyrealizedinthis case.

(12)

lesvieux c'est lanuit qu'onest malades

the old itis the night that wearesick

Inthisexample,thecleftinterpretation

isgivenbythesyntacticstructure(with

adislocated). This eect is reinforced

by a conclusive intonative contour on

thecleftNP.

(13)

latechno c'estlamusiquequ'onprefere

the techno thisisthe musicthat weprefer

Contrarily to the previous example, the pre-

ferredinterpretationisthatofarelative.Such

interpretation is given by the semanticlevel,

the generalform beingidentical with that of

the previous example. The intonation rein-

forcesthisinterpretation.

(14)

latechno c'est lamusique qu'onprefere

the techno this isthe musicthat weprefer

Aconclusiveintonation,rathertypicalofa

cleft, cannot beeasily realizedin this ex-

ample.

(15)

3 Basic Constraints

Theclassicaldescriptionofprosody/syntaxrelationisgenerallydonebymeansofconstraints

representingeitherthenecessityofaspecicrealizationoritsimpossibility. Intheperspective

of a constraint-based approach, thiskindof information isrepresented directly bymeans of

properties of the objects. This is the case for example of Property Grammars, described

in [Blache01], that rely on dierent kinds of constraints (e.g. requirement, exclusion, linear

precedence, etc.).

At this stage, it is possible to stipulate a rst set of constraints that will constitute a

preliminarystep inthedescriptionof therelations.

3.1 Describing an object with several components

A same linguisticobject isdescribed by meansof informationcomingfrom dierent compo-

nents. This characteristics is illustrated by several examples of the previous section. Let's

focus more precisely on examples 7-8. This case is apparently simple and regular. Indeed,

if thedataare veried, eachinterpretation (beingvocative ornot)is associated to a specic

intonative contour without possibility of variation. We obtain then the several constraints

that make itpossibleto precisesome principles.

[p1] SN[detached] ^Contour[conclusive] ) [-vocative]

(6)

(typicallya conclusive contour), takes a vocative interpretation. We are thenin the case of

a classical dislocation coming together with an anaphoric relation between the dislocated

NP and theclitic. The vocative interpretation described in [p2] impliesa detached NP plus

an intonational fall. In these constraints, the objects belong to three dierent components:

syntax, semanticsand prosody. It isnecessary to precise these domains. Moreover, itis also

necessary to precise their respective positions. The solution making it possible to build a

representation independently from any theoretical presuppositionconsists in indicating the

position of the object in the acoustic signal (cf. [Bird99]). This kindof indication is direct

for prosodicinformation, butdiÆcultto specifyforother domainssuchassyntax,semantics

or pragmatics. We propose (see [Blache03]) a general indexation mechanism specifying a

dierent kindof localization for any objects. We propose then to use an anchor containing

a dierent kindof indexation: localization in the signal, in the string or in the context. A

complex featurerepresentssuch anchorasfollows:

anchor! 2

4

temporal

i,j

position

k,l

contextc 3

5

Thetemporalindexisrepresentedbytwovalues(beginningandend). Thepositionisalso

a coupleofindexes(corresponding to nodes inachartinterpretation)localizingan objectin

the input. The context feature implements the notion of universe (i.e. a set of discourse

referents)asinDRT.Anobjectcanthenbespeciedbymeansofthree kindsofinformation:

its domain, its anchor and its characterization (the set of corresponding properties). The

followingexampledescribesan objectfrom thesyntactic domain, witha precise localization

bothon thetemporal andthe linearaxis:

obj! 2

6

6

6

4

domainsynt

anchor

"

temp

880,1000

position

2,3

#

charac

catDet

3

7

7

7

5

Asdetailedabove,constraints[p1]and[p2]areexpressedintermsofimplication. However,

thekindof relationrepresentedthereconsistsmorepreciselyinaco-variationofthedierent

values. Itismoreovernecessary,inparticular fortherepresentationofinformationat aner

levelthanthatoftheatomicobject,to expressanelementundertheformofasetoffeatures,

each one beingan attribute/value pair. This is thecase for exampleof a phoneme that can

be characterized by a set of segments or a syntactic category that corresponds to a set of

morphological, syntactic and semantic features. The relation[p2] concerns in fact dierent

featuresofasame objectcharacterizingasubpartoftheutterance. Thisobjectisrepresented

as follows:

p2! 2

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

4 synt

"

cat

NP

detached

pos

i,j

#

sem

type+vocative

pos

i,j

pros

contourcontinuative

3

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

5

(7)

ingfrom dierentcomponentsand participatingto thedescriptionof asame objector, more

generally, a same linguistic phenomenon. Each characteristic is associated with a position

in the signal represented by the complexfeature anchor. The dierent informationis still

representedseparately, thefeaturestructurebeinga wayfordescribing anobjectcontaining

features connectedwith some relations.

Thecovariationrelationspeciedaboveisexpressedbythespecicationofasimultaneous

variation of the value of some features in a structure. There are several ways to represent

this kind of relation, one of them being the useof \named disjunctions"(cf. [Kasper95] or

[Blache98]). Themechanismconsistsinenumeratingthesetofpossiblevaluesforeachfeature

and indicatingthevaluesthatareina mutualdependency. Allvaluesbelonging tothe same

part ofthedisjunctioncovary: whenavalueisinstantiated, thenallothervaluesof thesame

rank inthenamed disjunctionare also instantiated.

detached/dislocated ! 2

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

4 synt

2

4 cat

n

NP

detached

_1

NP

dislocated

o

anch

i,j

3

5

sem

"

type

+vocative_1 -vocative

anch

i,j

#

pros

"

contour

continuative_

1

conclusive

anch

i,j

# 3

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

5

In this example, the named disjunction is represented by _

1

. The values NP

detached ,

+vocative and continuative are then dependent (rst part of the disjunction), as well as

the values NP

disl ocated

, - vocative and conclusive. The previous structure works then as a

constraint on the concerned objects. As soon as an utterance description needs a set of

features speciedinthisstructure, theirvalueshave to satisfythe constraint.

3.2 Information on dierent parts of a same object

Aquickstudyofexamples9-14,describingcasesofcleftsandrelatives,exhibitsarstproperty

constraining the relative. This one is incompatible with a conclusive contour asin the case

of a cleft. This restrictionis representedby thefollowingconstraint stipulatingthata set of

categories constitutinga NP with a relative cannot be realized with an intonative stress on

the name,which correspondsto a parentheticcontour.

relative! 2

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

6

4 synt

2

6

4

*

catDet

anch

i,j

,

catN

anch

k,l

,

catRel

anch

m,n

+

anch

i,n

3

7

5

sem

type-focus

anch

i,l

pros

contourparenthetic

pos

i,l

3

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

7

5

In this example, we can remark on top of the constraint on the relative, the possibility

forasame objectto representinformationon dierentparts. Syntacticinformationconcerns

then theentirestructurewhereassemantic andprosodicinformationonlyconcernsa subset.

(8)

Thekindofconstraintspresentedabovecan representmanydierent relationsbetweencom-

ponents of linguistic analysis. However, itis impossible to provide generaldescriptions that

cannot be captured by covariation. In particular, it is diÆcult, or even impossible, using

such an approach to explain why prosodic realization seems less constrained under certain

circumstances. In the case of the distinction between clefts and relatives, a constraint can

characterize the general realization of the relative, but nothing can be said as for the cleft:

we can remark a great variability for this construction. Dierent corpus studies show that

it seems possibleto realizeclefts without any specic prosodic mark orwith many dierent

marks. The same phenomenon appears when a semantic featurereinforces a syntactic turn.

Thisisthecaseoftheexamples3-6thatpresentsomecasesofsimpleormultipledislocations.

In the case ofmultipledislocation(example3), two clitics are inan anaphoric relationwith

thedetachedNP.Inthiscase, wehave amorpho-syntacticcriterion(two cliticsagreeingwith

theNPs)plusasemanticindex(theanaphoricrelation). Wecanthenconsiderthat,whatever

theprosody,theinterpretationisconstrainedenoughbyinformationcomingfromsyntaxand

semantics. Onthe contrary, when theanaphoric relationdoesn'texist, asin theexamples 5

and 6,prosodyisstronglyconstrainedand playsan important roleintheinterpretation. For

example, thesecond realizationthat would considerthetwoNPs at thesame level(favoring

a doubledislocationinterpretation) isimpossible.

Generally speaking, we can consider that, when an utterance cannot be disambiguated

with a morpho-syntactic mark, thenthe prosody would play thisrole. In the examples 1-2,

intonationinitselfmakesitpossibletodistinguishbetweencausativeandcorrelativeinterpre-

tations. Moreclearly,inthecaseoftheexamples9-11,intonationdrivestheinterpretationas

relativeorcleft. Asalientturncannot be assignedto arelative,acleft interpretation isthen

favoredinthiscase. Cleftvariabilitywouldthencomefromthefactthatthisturnisstrongly

marked from amorpho-syntacticpointof view (morethantherelative). In thesame wayas

fordoubledislocation,morpho-syntacticandsemanticconstraintsarestrongenoughandthe

interpretationdoesn'tneedmoreinformation,forexampleaprosodicone. Thischaracteristic

is also clear inthe examples 12-14. Onecan observe inthesame waya syntactic variability

allowed by prosody. For example, a rising intonative contour is classically associated with

interrogative turns. We considerin thiscasethat theintonative schema is notvery ambigu-

ous, it can be associated with an heavy weight forprosody (in the same way as clefts have

an heavyweightforsyntax). Suchacharacteristicallowsvariabilityofthesyntacticform. In

a general way,and foranycomponent of linguisticanalysis,theweight value isproportional

to the ambiguity degree of the form. For example, a conclusive contour, specic to certain

constructions, or a major break are associated to heavy weights for prosody. In the same

way, marked syntactic constructions with strongmorpho-syntactic elements (such as clefts)

correspond to heavy syntactic weights.

There existsthen a relationbetween syntax,semantics and prosodythat cannot be rep-

resentedclassicallyintermsofcorrespondencesbetweentherespectivestructures. Morepre-

cisely,theonlyconstraintsthatcan be proposedinthisperspectivearethose ofcooccurency

restrictions, butwithoutproviding anaccount ofvariability.

Références

Documents relatifs

The correspondence between a semantic representation (= a predicate-argument structure) and a syntactic representation (= a surface syntactic dependency tree) of a

In [39] it is shown how the syntax of intuitionistic combinatorial proofs (or ICPs), a graphical proof system for propositional intuitionistic logic, provides some intuitive

It is thus natural to define obligations derived from the basic set as those sets of situations which satisfy the desirable properties of obligations defined via the order and

The segregation of the G blood-group alleles and the rob (15;17) marker was studied mostly in the large family of one boar whose linkage phase was known. The lod scores for this

Following development of the fetal bipotential gonad into a testis, male genital differentiation requires testicular androgens. Fetal Leydig cells produce testosterone that is

Nonaffected family members were healthy, with normal insulin secretion and action, except for two individuals displaying features typical of type 2 diabetes (advanced age at the

Ainsi dans le derme sont retrouvés les collagènes fibrillaires I, III et V, ainsi que les collagènes FACITs (―Fibril.. Associated Collagen with Interrupted

Firstly there is no need to introduce different syntactic types for different syntactic position of the quantifier: movement enables a single syntactic type to apply in