• Aucun résultat trouvé

Equality v. Conscience: The Dilemmas of Public Service Provision

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Partager "Equality v. Conscience: The Dilemmas of Public Service Provision"

Copied!
6
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

Preprint

Reference

Equality v. Conscience: The Dilemmas of Public Service Provision

LEVER, Annabelle

Abstract

Should Catholic adoption agencies be required to serve gay couples because they are willing to serve non-Catholics? Should Catholic hospitals be required to provide contraceptives to those who want them? Such questions lie at the heart of contemporary controversy, in Britain and the USA, over the appropriate scope for conscientious exemptions from antidiscrimination law, and over the implications of allowing voluntary associations a role in providing important public goods and services. Freedom of conscience requires that faith-based institutions be free to serve their members' needs in accordance with their religious teachings. But what should happen when faith-based institutions serve the general public, often with public funds?

There are two logically coherent but opposed answers to these questions: ‘conscience trumps all' and ‘equality trumps all'. Cardinal Timothy Dolan, Roman Catholic Archbishop of New York and President of the US Conference of Catholic Bishops, represents the first position, and the British Humanist Society represents the second. Both positions are too absolute to be persuasive. However, they [...]

LEVER, Annabelle. Equality v. Conscience: The Dilemmas of Public Service Provision.

Available at:

http://archive-ouverte.unige.ch/unige:26839

Disclaimer: layout of this document may differ from the published version.

1 / 1

(2)

Equality v Conscience ? dilemmas of public service provision Annabelle Lever

annabelle@alever.net Feb. 22 2013

Should Catholic adoption agencies be required to serve gay couples because they are willing to serve non-Catholics? Should Catholic hospitals be required to provide

contraceptives to those who want them? Such questions lie at the heart of contemporary controversy, in Britain and the USA, over the appropriate scope for conscientious

exemptions from antidiscrimination law, and over the implications of allowing voluntary associations a role in providing important public goods and services. Freedom of

conscience requires that faith-based institutions be free to serve their members’ needs in accordance with their religious teachings. But what should happen when faith-based institutions serve the general public, often with public funds?

There are two logically coherent but opposed answers to these questions: ‘conscience trumps all’ and ‘equality trumps all’. Cardinal Timothy Dolan, Roman Catholic Archbishop of New York and President of the US Conference of Catholic Bishops, represents the first position, and the British Humanist Society represents the second. Both positions are too absolute to be persuasive. However, they illuminate the complexities of the issues, and the scope for political choice in crafting morally acceptable solutions to these complex problems. 1

According to Cardinal Dolan, religious freedom requires conscientious exemptions from otherwise applicable laws for all religiously-affiliated hospitals, colleges and social service agencies, whether or not they provide services to the general public. For Dolan, then, conscience is as much implicated in the way Catholic-affiliated hospitals treat non-Catholic employees and patients as it is in the way that the Catholic Church handles purely internal

1 Of course, the vagaries of American Constitutional interpretation will likely constrain the scope for political choice facing Americans. But that does not mean that Americans should not be free to consider the moral issues first, and then ask themselves how best to clothe moral reflection in constitutional clothing.

(3)

matters, such as the selection of priests, or ministry to parishioners. Consequently, he claims, religious exemptions from non-discrimination laws that apply to the Church’s treatment of the faithful must apply to its provision of services to the general public.

Hence, he insists, if it is wrong to force the Catholic Church to make contraceptive and abortion care accessible to the faithful, it would be wrong to force it to provide insurance covering such care to non-Catholics working in Catholic schools and hospitals. 2 Similarly, Dolan maintains, if adoption services are precluded from serving gay couples when they minister only to the faithful, they must be allowed to discriminate against gay couples when they serve the general public.

According to the British Humanist Society, people’s claims to equality and non-

discriminatory public services mean that religious agencies must either abide by the same antidiscrimination norms as the State, or stick to providing goods and services to their co- religionists. Hence the Society’s report, ‘Quality and Equality: Human Rights, Public Services and Religious Organisations’, concludes that ‘all organisations involved in the provision of statutory public services should be secular ones, but if religious ones are to be given contracts, they must operate in an inclusive, secular manner’. 3

However, the difficulty with this view is that religious communities have an expressive interest in providing charitable services in accordance with their faith. Soup kitchens are not restaurants, and religiously-affiliated hospitals and public services have an expressive and charitable rationale which their for-profit equivalents lack. Thus, even if we agree with the humanists that voluntary associations must abide by norms applicable to the state, when they are acting ‘in loco statu’ , just as they must abide by norms applicable to parents, when they act ‘in loco parentis, we may still believe that conscientious

exemptions are sometimes justified.

Still, the limits of the idea that ‘equality trumps all’ do not mean that ‘conscience trumps all’. No one has a conscientious obligation to provide goods and services to the general

2 Cardinal Dolan’s views can be found in a 2012 article for the Wall Street Journal, available online at

https://docs.google.com/file/d/0B4ySwmbZuuI8NWQ0YmZlODUtYWJmMC00YWFkLWFkNjEtYjlkMmVlNzcz YzQy/edit?pli=1

3 .’Quality and Equality : Human Rights, Public Services and Religious Organisations’, a report of the British Humanist Association, available online at http://humanism.org.uk/campaigns/secularism/public-service- reform/quality-and-equality-report/ p. 21

(4)

public, whatever our duties to the poor and needy. Respect for conscience, therefore cannot require states to compromise the equality of their citizens, or their access to public services, simply because religious and secular associations sometimes seek to improve the lives of those who do not share their beliefs. Hence, states have no obligation to grant religious exemptions from generally applicable laws to those providing public services, whether or not the state itself is helping to subsidise them. In short, it is one thing to say that religious beliefs should determine religious care of the faithful, and quite another to say that they should determine the provision of non-profit goods and services for the general public.

There is therefore more scope for political choice in determining the extent of religious exemptions than is sometimes thought. Everyone has duties of charity, and these may lead us to serve those who do not share our ideals and convictions. But it is no violation of conscience when we are unable to provide those services because of state laws which protect our freedom and equality, or those of other people. On the other hand, there appear to be a range of cases in which states may, but need not, encourage the voluntary provision of public services, and where they may, but need not, grant conscientious exemptions from generally applicable laws. For example, states may wish to promote Jewish-Moslem cooperation in the provision of non-profit goods and services, and therefore to subsidise non-profit genetic counselling, or advice on domestic violence and hateful expression, even if this means accommodating the religious beliefs of their more traditional or orthodox members. However, states are obliged to ensure fair access to goods and services for citizens, and to protect their dignity. This means that states are entitled and, sometimes, obliged to seek alternatives to existing voluntary associations, and to favour those which will abide by non-discrimination norms over those which cannot.

Imagine two scenarios. In the first, a catholic adoption agency refuses to place children with same-sex couples in a city where there are many other adoption services, including gay-friendly ones. In the second, the same agency exercises a virtual monopoly over adoption services. In the former, accommodating the expressive interests of Catholics is compatible with protecting the self-respect and care of those ineligible for Catholic adoption services. This is not the case on the second scenario. Hence, in such

(5)

circumstances, the state would be entitled to remove any subsidies that it was providing to the Catholic agency, and to seek out and subsidise non-discriminatory adoption

services by others, or to provide them itself. Given the importance of adoption services to prospective parents, to the children involved, and to their birth parents, the state would have a duty to diminish the importance of any voluntary provider who was unable to abide by antidiscrimination norms, in order to meet its own obligations of non- discriminatory care to its citizens.

As we have seen, no state has a duty to support the charitable activities of religious groups in preference to other groups, and no state has a duty to support the charitable activities of groups- religious or not – who behave in a discriminatory fashion. That is the fundamental difficulty with the ‘conscience trumps all’ approach to the rights of non- profit public service providers. Indeed, the state has no duty to continue to support existing voluntary associations, in preference to alternatives. Those who are currently best placed to provide non-profit public services did not gain their position purely on merit. The relative capacity of different religious groups, different charitable groups and different providers of public services is still shaped by the legacy of undemocratic powers and privileges, inherited from the past. So while I have argued against forcing small religious associations to abide by antidiscrimination laws that violate their beliefs, states have duties to ensure that the powerful serve the public fairly. States are therefore entitled to promote non-profit associations which will abide by antidiscrimination norms, and may remove subsidies from existing associations in order to do so. This is not because equality is more important than freedom of conscience. Rather, it is because a

conscientious commitment to equality is a fragile achievement and, in a democracy, deserves state support.

1,432 words.

(6)

I am very grateful to Melissa Williams and Chiara Cordelli for help in sorting out my ideas.

They are certainly not to be blamed for the results. Cordelli’s own approach to these issues can be found at

http://socialsciences.exeter.ac.uk/politics/staff/cordelli/publications/.

Références

Documents relatifs

First it casts a sceptical eye on Cardinal Dolan’s expansive interpretation of freedom of conscience, which would require the State to enforce religious norms of

For example, Garrow’s study of the battles over the legalisation of contraception and abortion in New England paints a chilling picture of the willingness and ability of the

The operatives and direct supervisors thus massively express the desire to produce quality work at the service of identified users with whom they wish to maintain a

In this research, our review of literature indicated that the minimal e-readiness crite- ria for the implementation of SOA based “ubiquitous” e-government systems for public

It planned recurrent actions led by a specific Office, the new Office on International Religious Freedom, under the responsibility of the Under-Secretary for

And yet, France does not have a specific constitutional provision for artistic and literary creation as is the case in other European countries, with terms like cultural

It should be noted that in both countries central power has played a key part in assigning public services functions to local governments: in France, for a

At this equilibrium, when implementing the new value of the interest rate found inside the probabilities of choosing the low risk project and screening found