• Aucun résultat trouvé

A short proof of the strong normalization of the simply typed $\lambda\mu$-calculus

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "A short proof of the strong normalization of the simply typed $\lambda\mu$-calculus"

Copied!
6
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

HAL Id: hal-00382688

https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00382688

Submitted on 11 May 2009

HAL

is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers.

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire

HAL, est

destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés.

A short proof of the strong normalization of the simply typed λµ-calculus

René David, Karim Nour

To cite this version:

René David, Karim Nour. A short proof of the strong normalization of the simply typed

λµ-calculus.

Chambéry-Krakow-Lyon: workshop on

λ-calculus, type theory and mathematical logic, Computer

science department, Cracovic, Pologne, 27-28 Juin 2003, Jun 2003, Cracovic, Poland. pp.27-33. �hal-

00382688�

(2)

of the simply typed λµ-calculus

Ren´e DAVID and Karim NOUR LAMA - Equipe de Logique

Universit´e de Chamb´ery 73376 Le Bourget du Lac e-mail : {david,nour}@univ-savoie.fr

Abstract.We give an elementary and purely arithmetical proof of the strong normalization of Parigot’s simply typedλµ-calculus.

1. Introduction

This paper gives an elementary and purely arithmetical proof of the strong normal- ization of the cut-elimination procedure for the implicative propositional classical logic, i.e. the propositional calculus with the connectives →and ⊥. As usual, ⊥ codes the absurdity and the negation is defined by ¬A=A→⊥.

This proof is based on a proof of the strong normalization of the simply typed λ-calculus due to the first author (see [2]) which, itself, is a simplification of the one given by R. Matthes in [3]. After this paper had been written we were told by P.L. Curien and some others that this kind of technique was already present in van Daalen (see [8]) and J.J. Levy (see [4]).

Since the proofs in the implicative propositional classical logic can be coded by Parigot’s λµ-terms and the cut elimination corresponds to the λµ-reduction, the result can be seen as a proof of the strong normalization of the simply typed λµ- calculus. The first proof of the the strong normalization of theλµ-calculus for the types of Girard’s system F was done by Parigot in [6] in two different ways : by using reducibility candidates and by a CPS transformation to the λ-calculus.

The technique we present here can also be used to prove the strong normalization of the cut elimination procedure for the classical natural deduction (i.e. where all the connectives, in particular ∨, are present and permutative conversions are considered) but more elaborate ideas are necessary. This result was proved (see [1]) by using a CPS transformation. We will give a direct proof in a forthcoming paper.

(3)

2

2. The typed system

Theλµ-terms, which extend theλ-terms, are given by the following grammar (where x, y, ... are variables):

T ::=x|λxT |(T T)|µxT

The new constructorµcorresponds to the classical rule⊥c given below.

Γ, x:A⊢x:Aax Γ, x:A⊢M :B Γ⊢λxM:A→B →i

Γ1⊢M :A→B Γ2⊢N :A

Γ12⊢(M N) :B →e Γ, x:¬A⊢M :⊥ Γ⊢µxM :A ⊥c The cut-elimination procedure corresponds to the reduction rules given below.

A logical cutappears when the introduction of the connective→is immediately followed by its elimination. The reduction rule is the usual β reduction of the λ-calculus:

(λxM N)→M[x:=N]

A classical cut appears when the classical rule is immediately followed by the elimination rule of→. The reduction rule is :

(µxM N)→µyM[x:=λz(y(z N))]

It corresponds to the following transformation on the proofs (written in the natural deduction style):

[¬(A→B)]

D1

⊥ A→B

D2 A B

[¬B]

[A→B] D2

A B

¬(A→B) D1

⊥ B

This coding, though slightly different from the one in [6], is essentially the same and the two systems are obviously equivalent.

- Parigot uses two sets of variables: the λ-variables (for the intuitionistic as- sumptions) and the µ-variables (for classical assumptions, i.e. the ones that are discharged by the absurdity rule⊥c). Moreover his typing judgements have several conclusions.

- We use only one set of variables and sequents with only one conclusion. Thus, we do not need the new constructor [α] and the corresponding notion of substitu- tion. The drawback is that the reduction introduces some “administrative” redexes.

These notations and reductions rules are the ones used in the λ of Rehof and Sorensen (see [7]).

(4)

3. Strong normalization

We first need some notations and lemmas.

3.1. Lemmas for the un-typed calculus

Notation 3..1 LetM be aλµ-term.

1. M →M (resp. M → M) means that M reduces toM by using one step (resp. some steps) of the reduction rules given above.

2. cxty(M)is the number of symbols occurring inM.

3. M is strongly normalizable (this is denoted byM ∈SN) if there is no infinite sequence ofreductions. If M ∈ SN, η(M) is the length of the longest reduction ofM.

4. −→

N (resp. −→

λµ) represents a sequence ofλµ-terms (resp. ofλorµabstractions).

If−→

N is the sequenceN1...Nn,(M −→

N)denotes theλµ-term(M N1...Nn).

5. In a proof by induction,IH will denote the induction hypothesis.

Lemma 3..1 Every λµ-term M can be written as −→ λµ(R −→

O)where R is either a redex (called the head-redex of M) or a variable (in this case,M is in head normal form).

Proof By induction oncxty(M).

Definition 3..1 LetM be aλµ-term.

1. hred(M)is the term obtained fromM by reducing its head-redex, if any.

2. arg(M) is the set of terms defined by:

• arg(−→

λµ(x O1...On)) ={O1, ..., On}.

• arg(−λµ(λxP Q O→ 1...On)) =arg(−λµ(µxP Q O→ 1...On)) ={P, Q, O1, ..., On}.

Lemma 3..2 Let M, N be λµ-terms. Then, arg(M[x:=N])⊂arg(N)∪ {N} ∪ {Q[x:=N]/ Q∈arg(M)}.

Proof Immediate.

Lemma 3..3 Let M be a λµ-term. Then, M ∈ SN iff arg(M) ⊂ SN and hred(M)∈SN.

Proof ⇒is immediate. ⇐: IfM =−→ λµ(x−→

O) the result is trivial.

- IfM =−→ λµ(R−→

O) whereR=λxP Q: sincearg(M)⊂SN, an infinite reduction ofM must look like: M →−→

λµ(λxP1 Q1−O→1)→−→

λµ(P1[x:=Q1]−O→1)→ ... . The result immediately follows from the fact that (P[x:=Q]−→

O)→(P1[x:=Q1]−→ O1).

- IfM =−→

λµ(R−→O) whereR=µxP Q: the proof is similar.

(5)

4

Lemma 3..4 Let M ∈SN be λµ-term. Then (M y)∈SN.

Proof We prove by induction on (η(M), cxty(M)) that, if M ∈ SN, then (M[σ]y)∈SN whereσis a substitution of the form : [x1:=λu(x1(u y)), ..., xn :=

λu(xn (u y))]. It follows immediately from the IH that, ifN is a strict sub-term of M, then N[σ] ∈SN and thus arg((M[σ]y))⊂SN. By lemma 3..3, it is thus enough to prove that N = hred((M[σ]y)) ∈ SN. In each case the result follows easily from the IH:

• IfM = (x−→

O) andσ(x) =x: then (M[σ]y) = (x−−→

O[σ]y).

• IfM = (x O1−→

O) andσ(x) =λu(x(u y): thenN = (x(O1[σ]y)−→ O[σ]y).

• If M = (λxP Q −→O): then N = (M[σ]y) where M = hred(M) and thus η(M)< η(M).

• IfM = (µxP Q−→

O): similar.

• IfM =λxP: thenN=P[σ][x:=y].

• IfM =µxP: thenN =µxP[σ] whereσ =σ∪[x:=λu(x(u y))].

3.2. Proof of the strong normalization of the typed calculus

The following result is straightforward.

Lemma 3..5 If Γ⊢M :A andM →N thenΓ⊢N :A.

Lemma 3..6 Let M ∈ SN be a λµ-term and σ be a substitution. Assume that the substituted variables all have the same type and, for all x, σ(x)∈ SN. Then M[σ]∈SN.

Proof This is done by induction on (lgt(σ), η(M), cxty(M), η(σ)) where lgt(σ) is the number of connectives in the type of the substituted variables and η(σ) is the sum of the η(N) for the N that are actually substituted, i.e. for example if σ = [x := N] and x occurs n times in M, then η(σ) = n.η(N). The cases M =λxP,M =µxP and M = (y−→

P) fory6=xare trivial. Otherwise, by theIH and lemma 3..2, arg(M[σ])⊂SN. By lemma 3..3 it is thus enough to show that hred(M[σ])∈SN:

• IfM = (λyP Q−→

O) : hred(M[σ]) =hred(M)[σ] and the result follows from theIH sinceη(hred(M))< η(M).

• M = (µyP Q−→

O) : similar.

• M = (x P −→

O) : by our definition of η(σ), we may assume, without loss of generality, thatxoccurs only once inM. Let N =σ(x).

– IfN is not in head normal form,hred(M[σ]) =M[σ] whereσ(y) =σ(y) fory 6=xand σ(x) = hred(N). The result follows from the IH since η(σ)< η(σ).

– IfN= (y−→

N1), the result is trivial.

(6)

– If N = λyN1 then hred(M[σ]) = (N1[y := P[σ]] −−→

O[σ]). By the IH, since lgt(P[σ]) < lgt(σ), N1[y := P[σ]] ∈ SN and thus, by the IH, hred(M[σ]) = (z −−→

O[σ]) [z := N1[y := P[σ]]] ∈ SN since lgt(N1) <

lgt(σ).

– IfN =µyN1 thenM[σ] = (µyN1P[σ]−−→

O[σ]). Let M1 = (µyN1z) where z is a fresh variable. By lemma 3..4, M1 ∈ SN. Since lgt(P[σ]) <

lgt(σ), by the IH, (µyN1P[σ]) = M1[z := P[σ]] ∈ SN. But M[σ] = M2[u := (µyN1P[σ])] where M2 = (u−−→

O[σ]) and u is a fresh variable.

Sincelgt((µyN1P[σ]))< lgt(σ), the result follows from the theIH.

Theorem 3..1 Every typedλµ-term is strongly normalizable.

Proof By induction oncxty(M). The casesM =x, M =λx N or M =µx N are trivial. If M = (N1 N2) the result follows from lemma 3..6 and the IH since

M = (x N2)[x:=N1] wherexis a fresh variable.

Remarks

1. In the proof of theorem 3..1, the caseM = (N1 N2) can also be solved, by writingM = (N1 x)[x:= N2] where x is a fresh variable and using lemma 3..3.

2. In the proof of lemma 3..4, the caseM = (x P −→

O) andN =λyN1 can be solved exactly as the case N =µyN1 by usingM1 = (λyN1z) where z is a fresh variable.

4. References

[1] P. de Groote.Strong normalization of classical natural deduction with disjunc- tion. TLCA’01 in Lecture Notes in Computer Science (2044), pp. 182-196.

Springer Verlag, 2001.

[2] R. David.Normalization without reducibility. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic (107), p. 121-130, 2001.

[3] F. Joachimski and R. Matthes. Short proofs of normalization for the simply- typed lambda-calculus, permutative conversions and G¨odel’s Tin Arch. Math.

Logic 42, p 59-87 (2003).

[4] J.J. Levy. Rductions correctes et optimales dans le lambda-calcul. PhD thesis Paris 7, 1978.

[5] M. Parigotλµ-calculus: An algorithm interpretation of classical natural deduc- tion.Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence (624), pp. 190-201. Springer Verlag 1992.

[6] M. Parigot.Proofs of strong normalization for second order classical natural deduction. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 62 (4), pp. 1461-1479, 1997.

[7] N.J. Rehof and M.H. Sorensen.Theλ-calculus.TACS’94 in Lecture Notes in Computer Science (789), pp. 516-542. Springer Verlag, 1994.

[8] D. van DaalenThe language theory of Automath. PhD Thesis. Eindhoven 1977.

Références

Documents relatifs

De Groote (2001) introduced the typed λµ ∧∨ -calculus to code the classical natural deduction system, and showed that it enjoys the main important properties: the strong

It is well known that, when the underlying logic is the classical one (i.e. the absurdity rule is allowed) these connectives are redundant since, for example, ∨ and ∧ can be coded

In this paper, we present an extension of λµ-calculus called λµ ++ - calculus which has the following properties: subject reduction, strong normalization, unicity of the

The strong normalization theorem of second order classical natural deduction [20] is based on a lemma known as the correctness result, which stipulates that each term is in

The strong normalization of a typed λµ-calculus can be deduced from the one of the corresponding typed λ-calculus by using CPS translations. See, for example, [14] for such

This paper gives a semantical proof of the strong normalization of the cut-elimination procedure for full propositional classical logic written in natural deduction style.. By full

In section 5, we give an example showing that the proofs of strong normalization using candidates of reducibility must somehow be different from the usual ones and we show that, in

This follows immediately from the strong normalization of the calculus of substitution (i.e. all the rules except b) which is proved in [4]2. We have stated the previous lemma in