• Aucun résultat trouvé

Independence in judgment aggregation

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Partager "Independence in judgment aggregation"

Copied!
2
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

Independence in judgment aggregation

Gabriella Pigozzi, Marija Slavkovik, and Leendert van der Torre University of Luxembourg, Computer Science and Communications

{gabriella.pigozzi,marija.slavkovik,leon.vandertorre}@uni.lu

Judgment aggregation is a rapidly developing research area in economics which at- tracts the interest of several fields, such as law, political science and philosophy [3].

It studies how the individual opinions of an agent, which are opinions on logically interconnected propositions, can be mapped into a collective judgment on the same propositions. Dietrich and List showed that judgment aggregation is a generalization of the aggregation issues discussed in Arrow’s impossibility theorem [1]. Whereas so- cial choice theory studies the aggregation of individual preferences in order to select a collectively preferred alternative, judgment aggregation explores how to combine indi- vidual judgments on specific propositions.

Unfortunately, likewise social choice theory, the field of judgment aggregation is plagued by impossibility results (see, for example, [4, 6]), which generally state that there exists no aggregation rule that generates complete, consistent and deductively closed collective sets of judgments, while satisfying a set of seemingly rational condi- tions. The conditions imposed on the aggregation rule aim to ensure the rationality and the systematic approach of the aggregation procedure. The first impossibility result [4]

contained that all consistent and complete judgment sets are being considered for the joint outcome (Universal Domain), and that all agents opinions are equally contributing to the joint outcome (Anonymity). In addition, a (Systematicity) rule is imposed, which ensures that the collective judgment on each proposition depends only on the individual judgments on that proposition, and that the aggregation rule remains the same across all propositions.

The hope for possibility results is seen in re-examining and relaxing these conditions and, with systematicity being considered the most controversial, it has been weekend to an Independence condition. The independence of irrelevant alternatives condition is systematicity without the neutrality condition, requiring that all propositions are equally treated. Just like Arrow’s independence condition plays a central role in his famous impossibility theorem, the similar requirement leads to impossibility results in judgment aggregation.

However, these formal frameworks ignore an important distinction between aggre- gating judgments and preferences, which becomes apparent in our study of the bench- mark examples of these areas. In this paper we start by arguing that the distinction between the premises and conclusions play an important role in the benchmark exam- ples of judgment aggregation. By considering the notion of independence in judgment aggregation frameworks, we observe that the distinction between premises and conclu- sion is not taken into account. In these frameworks, the conclusion(s), individually or jointly obtained, are logically dependent on the corresponding premises. However, the premises are independent from each other.

(2)

Based on our analysis, we introduce new independence assumptions that capture the distinction between premises and conclusions. Recently, Mongin and Dietrich and Mongin [5, 2] further relaxed Independence. We use Mongin’s framework, because his notion of independence of irrelevant propositional alternatives enables us to formulate our new independence assumptions and to define our operators based on a partition between premise and conclusion propositions. In particular, we define:

1. A strong notion of premise independence, where the aggregated premise propo- sitions depend on the individual judgments of this proposition, as well as on the aggregated conclusion propositions.

2. A weak notion of premise independence, where the aggregated premise proposi- tions depend on the individual judgments of this proposition, as well as on the individual and aggregated conclusion propositions.

3. A strong notion of conclusion independence, where the aggregated conclusion propo- sitions depend on the individual judgments of this proposition, as well as on the aggregated premise propositions.

4. A weak notion of conclusion independence, where the aggregated conclusion propo- sitions depend on the individual judgments of this proposition, as well as on the individual and aggregated premise propositions.

Since in most cases there will be several premise propositions and only one conclu- sion proposition, as in the standard example of the doctrinal paradox in the literature, the first two assumptions will be more often used than the latter ones. Of the first two, the strong notion already enables several interesting operators, which we illustrate using the revised conclusion procedure and the conclusion dictator. In both cases the aggregation may in some cases depend on the aggregated conclusion. For example, the conclusion dictator ensures that the joint decision is always determined by herself, but he allows the other individuals to influence the reasons why her decision is justified.

References

1. F. Dietrich and C. List. Arrow’s theorem in judgment aggregation.Social Choice and Welfare, 2006.

2. F. Dietrich and P. Mongin. The premiss-based approach to judgment aggregation. Working paper, 2007.

3. C. List. Judgment aggregation - a bibliography on the discursive dilemma, the doctrinal paradox and decisions on multiple propositions.

http://personal.lse.ac.uk/LIST/doctrinalparadox.htm.

4. C. List and P. Pettit. Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result.Economics and Philosophy, 18:89–110, 2002.

5. P. Mongin. Factoring out the impossibility of logical aggregation. Journal of Economic Theory.

6. C. Nehring. The impossibility of a paretian ratonal.Working paper, 2005.

Références

Documents relatifs

Here we produce other families of grid graphs, with open or cylindric boundary conditions, for which similar properties hold without any size restriction: the number of independent

The third variant (Theo- rem 5.8 (b), in Section 5) is a linear independence statement in the dual algebra of a bialgebra; namely, it claims that (again under certain conditions) a

Using about 950000 hadronic events collected during 1991 and 1992 with the ALEPH detector, the ratios r b = bs = udsc s and r uds = uds s = cbs have been measured in order to test

In an attempt to understand what might be the notion of boundary values in the smooth, as opposed to real-analytic, setting we consider in Section 4 of the paper an example that

We can conclude from the simulation experiments in this section that the mixture approach is preferred when we want to estimate the effects of explanatory variables which are

In this paper, we study independent broadcasts of caterpillars and give an explicit formula for the broadcast independence number of caterpillars having no pair of adjacent trunks,

This set is known as the Gaussian Unitary Ensemble (GUE) and corresponds to the case where a n × n hermitian matrix M has independent, complex, zero mean, Gaussian distributed

For instance, it is a well-known fact (see [14, Section 3]) that non-zero random variables living inside a xed Wiener chaos of order q > 3 are not necessarily moment-determinate,