• Aucun résultat trouvé

The equivalence principle meets the uncertainty principle

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Partager "The equivalence principle meets the uncertainty principle"

Copied!
9
0
0

Texte intégral

(1)

A NNALES DE L ’I. H. P., SECTION A

D ANIEL M. G REENBERGER

The equivalence principle meets the uncertainty principle

Annales de l’I. H. P., section A, tome 49, n

o

3 (1988), p. 307-314

<http://www.numdam.org/item?id=AIHPA_1988__49_3_307_0>

© Gauthier-Villars, 1988, tous droits réservés.

L’accès aux archives de la revue « Annales de l’I. H. P., section A » implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www.numdam.

org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou impression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la présente mention de copyright.

Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques

http://www.numdam.org/

(2)

307

The Equivalence Principle

Meets the Uncertainty Principle

Daniel M. GREENBERGER (*)

Max Planck Institut fur

Quantcnoptik,

D-8046 Garching b. Munchen, FRG

Vol. 49, 3, 1988, 1 Physique theorique

ABSTRACT. 2014 We

argue

that the very existence of the weak

Equivalence Principle

can

only

be understood in terms of the

Uncertainty Principle.

RESUME. 2014 Nous

presentons

des

arguments

montrant que 1’existence meme du

Principe d’Equivalence

Faible ne

peut

etre

comprise qu’en

relation avec Ie

Principe

d’lncertitude.

Louis De

Broglie

was, as was Albert

Einstein,

a master iconoclast

2014a constant

challenger

of

universally

held

myths.

It is in this

grand,

but

difficult,

tradition of

being willing

to step on every- one’s toes, that Jean-Pierre

Vigier

was trained as De

Broglie’s assistant,

and in which he has

fully

matured. Not

only

in his

professional

life as a

physicist,

but in his

private

life as

well,

has he set his own direction and followed his own conscience.

In the same

spirit

I would like to tell you

why

I think the search for a

classical unified field

theory

failed. I think it also

explains why

I expect the search for a

quantized

version of

gravity

to also fail. It is

primarily

because I believe the search is

heading

in the

totally

wrong direction. The

problem

is not the mathematical

complexity

of the

theory,

but rather that the

physics

is wrong. I believe that there are still many clues

being

offered

by

the

equivalence principle,

and

insights

into this

principle,

that we have

not made use of. And

they

lead in a

totally

different direction.

(I recognize

(*) Permanent Address: Dept. of Physics, City College of New York, New York, N. Y.

10031, USA.

Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré - Physique theorique - 0246-0211

Vol. 49/88/03/307/ 8 /$ 2,80/(0 Gauthier-Villars

(3)

308 D. M. GREENBERGER

that

electrodynamics

has been combined with the weak interaction. None- theless I believe that there is a unification with

gravity

to be

had, only

that

it will

proceed along

very different lines than have so far been

investigated.)

I believe that the very existence of the weak

equivalence principle

can

only

be understood in terms of the

uncertainty principle,

and I will try here to

explain

this. It is easiest to describe these ideas in terms of a

simple

extension of

special relativity,

which takes the mass more

seriously

as a

dynamical

variable.

(The

details of this

theory

were worked out in Ref.

[1 ].) Specifically,

the

theory

says that in fact we live not in a 4-dimensional

spacetime continuum,

but rather in a 5-dimensional one, and the fifth dimension is not a

hidden, folded-up,

mathematical

fiction,

but is as real

as the other four. It is the proper

time,

which should be treated as an inde-

pendent degree

of freedom.

Why?

Because like any true

degree

of

freedom,

we can not

only arbitrarily

set

it,

but we can

arbitrarily

determine its rate of

change.

One can

always (in principle)

erect a

spherical

mass sheet around a

region

and this will affect the

gravitational potential inside,

and hence the rate at which the proper time of a

particle

runs relative to coordinate

time

there,

without

exerting

any forces in the

region

or otherwise

disrupting

the local

physics. (Thus

it is

only

the second

derivative,

the « acceleration » of the proper

time,

that is affected

by

the laws of

motion.)

The

dynamical

variable

conjugate

to the proper time is the mass, and

together they

enter the Hamiltonian of the

problem

in the same way

as x and p. This in turn determines the

equations

of

motion,

which

yield

not

only x

as a function of the

time, t,

but also the proper

time,

’r, as a func- tion of t

(so

that this needs no

longer

to be

postulated

as part of the kine-

matics). Also, just

as p can

change

as a function of

time,

so too can m

change

as a function of time. Thus the

theory

is a classical

theory

of

changing

mass, and

represents

a new and

simple

way to treat

decaying particles,

even

classically.

But for our purposes, we

merely

write as an

illustration,

the Hamiltonian for a

free,

stable

particle

Now in

ordinary physics, m

here is

just

a parameter, and there is no

expla-

nation for the symmetry between m and p.

However the

independent

variables here are x and ’t", to be determined

as

f(t) by solving

the

equations

of motion. Their

conjugate

variables are

p and m. For a free

particle

the

change of p

and m are

given by

which

merely

says that momentum and 0 mass are conserved 0

here,

as is

Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré - Physique " theorique

(4)

expected.

But one sees that

just

as one could have H

depend

on x,

producing

a force which

changes

p, one could

equally

as well make H

depend

on ’t,

which would

produce

a « force » that would

change

the mass of the

particle.

Yet even at this

simple level,

there is further information to be

gained,

for the other

equations

are

These

equations

determine

and also

So this latter

equation

need not be

postulated separately,

as a property of the

metric,

but follows

directly

from the symmetry of the

theory.

In a

sense, when you were

taught relativity,

you were

taught only

half of the

subject. (Also,

in this

theory,

if the

particle decays,

this will affect the rate of passage of proper

time.)

It is not necessary here to consider a more

complicated

system. We

merely

have to

point

out that in this

dynamics,

besides the usual

uncertainty principles

there is a new one

This last

equation

says that when one tries to measure the mass, or the proper

time, directly,

there is a limit to the combined accuracy of the two, which is determined

by ordinary

quantum considerations.

For

example,

let us assume we want to measure the mass,

M,

of a

heavy particle by gravitationally scattering

off of it a

light particle

of known

mass, m, and

velocity v (see

the

figure).

The time of maximum

interaction, T,

is

given by

The transverse momentum

picked

up

by

the

light particle

will be

Vol. 49, n° 3-1988.

(5)

310 D. M. GREENBERGER

FIG. 1. - The Uncertainty Principle for Mass and Proper Time. If one measures the mass M of a heavy particle by scattering a light mass off of it gravitationally, then the angle 8 deter-

mines M. But the light particle exerts an unknown gravitational potential on M, to the

extent that b is unknown, so that ~, where T is the proper time read by a

clock located on M.

and the deflection will be

approximately (for

small

9)

which

yields

a measure of M. But also

This

gives

both the mass and the accuracy to which it is known.

However if there were a clock

sitting

on

particle M,

then even if we knew

its time

exactly

before we

performed

the

experiment,

we would no

longer

know it

accurately

after the

experiment

has been

performed.

This is because

while the

light particle passed by,

it exerted a

gravitational potential

on

M,

which will affect the clock

reading.

If the distance b is known to within

5b,

then

and one has

So the extent to which one can

accurately

measure the mass of the

particle

limits the

knowledge

one has of its proper

time,

and vice versa.

One sees that this

only depends

on the usual

uncertainty principle

between

py and y,

operating

on the

light particle,

and so is unavoidable.

(For

further

examples

of the

uncertainty principle,

see the second paper of ref.

[1 ].)

There are any number of

examples

of this

type,

and

they

all show that as

long

as there is an

uncertainty

relation between E and t, and p and x, then there must be one between m and r.

It seems to me that this

uncertainty principle

between m and 03C4 leads

Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré - Physique theorique

(6)

to an

important insight

into the nature of the weak

equivalence principle,

because this

principle

states that in an external

gravitational

field the motion of a

particle

is

independent

of its mass, m.

Thus,

in an external

gravitational

field one may know the mass very

poorly,

and yet still

accurately

determine the

position

and

velocity

of the

particle.

In other

words,

one can have

(nonrelativistically)

So without

violating

the

uncertainty principle,

one can know the

trajectory

of a

particle

very

accurately, provided

one does not know its mass, because in this case, one can know the

velocity

without

knowing

the momentum.

But this

situation,

so

totally

different from the usual quantum case where

one cannot know

trajectories,

is

possible only

because of the

equivalence principle.

For

example, Kepler’s

law states that for a

particle

in a circular

orbit in a field with a

1/r potential, independently

of

the mass of the

orbiting particle

m. Thus even if m is very

poorly

known

(indeed,

because it is

poorly known),

one can measure the radius r accu-

rately,

and determine the

period

T

accurately

and therefore calculate the

velocity v (= 27rr/T)

and the proper time 1"

(= ~/1 - r~/c~).

Therefore one very

important

index of the

equivalence principle

is that

it allows one to work in the limit

Of course one can have intermediate cases where m is known to some

extent. But because the mass

drops

out of the

equation

of motion in an

external

gravity field,

it

gives

rise to this very

special

property, that one

can determine

trajectories.

This is to be

strongly

contrasted with the case in

ordinary

quantum

theory,

where we

usually

know the mass

fairly accurately.

But in that situation

we know almost

nothing

about the proper

time,

T2014a statement that needs to be

explained.

In our discussion we have assumed that one is

going

to measure m.

This measurement

yields

the

uncertainty

relation ~. Even if one

assumes that r was

accurately

known before the

experiment,

the uncertain- ties introduced

by

the act of measurement will

destroy

this

knowledge

to the extent necessary. If one does not

perform

such an

experiment

but

assumes, say, that one has an

electron,

then one must ask « Since when has this electron been

around,

in order to start the clock for ’t

running ?

».

If it is a stable

particle,

then Om =

0,

and one has no idea when it was

created,

and Ar=oo.Ifit is an unstable

particle

one

usually

writes

~,

Vol. 49, 3-1988.

(7)

312 D. M. GREENBERGER

where ~E is the width of the

particle,

and Ot is the lifetime. But in fact this « DE » is

really

a mass

uncertainty. Similarly,

there is no real Ot asso-

ciated with the

particle one

may know the

laboratory

time

quite

accura-

tely.

It is more

properly

a statement about the

uncertainty

of a clock located

on the

particle,

that runs so

long

before the

particle decays.

So many of

our usual lifetime-width

uncertainty

relations are more

appropriately represented

as mass-proper time relations.

The above relates to the case where the mass is taken as «

given

», and

one does not set about to determine it

experimentally.

If

instead,

a

particle decays,

and one wants to know what

product

one

has,

one can measure

its mass, and

thereby

reset the proper

time,

L, as

described,

but

only

to the

extent

governed by

the

uncertainty principle.

So L can be

naturally

« set »

by

the formation of the

particle,

or later « reset »

by

a

specific experiment,

one

measuring

the mass, or r

directly.

When the mass is taken as

given,

the usual case in

quantum theory,

and

one

applies

an electric

(or

other

non-gravitational)

field to accelerate the

particle,

the usual restrictions on its orbit

apply,

and one cannot

accurately

know its

trajectory,

which is needed to calculate r. As described

above,

one does not know L because one does not know when to start

counting.

Over and above

that,

there is an extra

uncertainty

because of ones lack of

knowledge

of the

trajectory.

Even in the case when one

ignores

the initial lack of

knowledge

of L, and tries to determine the passage of r since the start of the

experiment,

one will be limited

by

the mass-proper time uncer-

tainty relation,

where now Om will be

DE/c2.

One can consider this expe- riment to be a new measure of the mass, and L, but after the

system

loses its

coherence, Ar

will become infinite

again.

So one can measure Ar in this manner in an external

non-gravitational field,

even if the initial mass is

known,

and the

experiment

then

yields

a

finite Ar. However there will be a minimum

possible

Ar that one can obtain

in such an

experiment.

One cannot make Ar =

0,

because one cannot

gain complete knowledge

of the

trajectory.

For a free

particle,

the best

one can do is determined

by

the fact that

Here,

one does not know to, the creation

time,

at

all,

as we have discussed.

However,

if one wants to make a new determination

ofr,

one will be limited

by

the fact that

(assuming

for convenience a nonrelativistic

particle)

one

can not know both E and t

simultaneously,

even

though

one would need

to, in order to determine ’L, since

If m is taken as

known,

then

Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré - Physique " theorique "

(8)

One can then take and minimize Ar with respect to At. One finds

approximately

and one sees that Ar grows in time. For a neutron, one would find that

over its lifetime there is a cumulated

uncertainty

1 cm,

although

in

practice,

it would

likely

be a

good

deal

longer.

We are now in a

position

to see that the

equivalence principle places

classical

electromagnetic

and

gravitational

fields in a

unique perspective.

In an external

gravitational field,

one need not know the mass at

all,

and yet one can

accurately

measure the

trajectory

of

particles,

and one can

then be in the situation where

On the other hand in an electric

field,

one often knows the mass

exactly,

and one can be in the situation where

Of course, in either case one may have

partial knowledge

of either

variable,

but the distinction between the extreme cases comes about because of the

equivalence principle.

The two cases shown above

correspond

to two

opposite

extremes of the

uncertainty relation,

much as in the case of wave

vs.

particle knowledge

in

ordinary

quantum

theory.

In that case, which

we are used to, one says that a quantum mechanical

object

is

subject

to

quantum

laws,

which in the two extremes reduce to the classical charac- terisation as

particle

motion or wave motion. In

general,

neither is an

adequate

characterisation.

I would characterise the combined

gravitational

and

electromagnetic

field as a quantum

field,

which in the two extreme limits can be characterised

as a

gravitational field, subject

to the

equivalence principle,

or else as an

electromagnetic

field. In

general

it is

something

more

complicated

than

either.

(I

do not think the weak interaction

changes

this

scheme.)

So I would

expect

the search for a unified field to

produce

this

fully

quantum mechanical

entity, governed by

the

uncertainty principle,

which

is neither electrical nor

gravitational

in nature. It is

only

in the extreme

limits that we can characterise it as a classical field of one nature or the other.

Only

when this

generalized

field is understood will it become

possible

to tackle the

problem

we refer to as « quantum

gravity ».

I suspect that if present attempts to

quantize

classical

gravity

were to

succeed,

it would

be a serious setback for

physics,

since everyone would rush to accept the

theory,

which would

probably

be wrong, and there would be no way to test it.

In the

light

of these

remarks,

one can see that I believe that our present

Vol. 49, 3-1988.

(9)

314 D. M. GREENBERGER

ideas as to the nature of

gravitational

and

electromagnetic

fields are still

hopelessly naive,

from the

standpoint

of a « final »

theory.

I would not for

a moment

question

the mathematical

sophistication

of present

theories,

but I believe that there are still many

physical insights

that we have not

made use of.

Certainly

the

equivalence principle

still has much to teach us.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

I would like to thank Prof. Herbert Walther and the Max Planck Institut fur

Quantenoptik

for the wonderful

hospitality

afforded me

during

my

stay

here,

and also the Alexander von Humboldt

Stiftung

for their support

during

this

period,

as well as the

City College

of the

City University

of

New York.

[1] D. M. GREENBERGER, J. Math. Physics, t. 11, 1970, p. 2329 ; t. 11, 1970, p. 2341 ; t. 15, 1974, p. 395 ; t. 15, 1974, p. 406.

(Manuscrit reçu le 10 juillet 1988)

Annales de Henri Poincaré - Physique theorique

Références

Documents relatifs

Considering that the electromagnetic field is a special case of the gravitational field [10], the structure of which has the character of a standing gravitational wave for

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des

MICROSCOPE is a French Space Agency mission that aims to test the Weak Equivalence Principle in space down to an accuracy of 10 − 15.. This is two orders of magnitude better than

Abstract: As an analogue of the classical uncertainty inequality on the Euclidean space, we shall obtain a generalization on the Sturm-Liouville hypergroups ðR þ ; ðAÞÞ.. Especially,

Then the data term of the optical flow formulation is based on a stochastic transport equation, derived from a location uncertainty principle [17].. In addition, a

One implication of Theorem 4 is that, if we were to consider only the admissible signals in C N as windows – which is not unreasonable in many applications since one would like to

Now it is possible to write the quantum Hamiltonian of a particle moving in an external Yang-Mills field; to this end consider the following potentials:.. The

To expand partition functions in terms of contours, we introduce the notion of disordered « dis » boundary conditions. In accordance with defi- nitions of Section